nl-kr-request@CS.ROCHESTER.EDU (NL-KR Moderator Brad Miller) (02/02/88)
NL-KR Digest (2/01/88 23:55:15) Volume 4 Number 13 Today's Topics: Re: failure of TM Gross's article the Gospel according to Newmeyer the imaginary worlds of grammarians Submissions: NL-KR@CS.ROCHESTER.EDU Requests, policy: NL-KR-REQUEST@CS.ROCHESTER.EDU ---------------------------------------------------------------------- Date: Mon, 25 Jan 88 17:46 EST From: Rick Wojcik <rwojcik@bcsaic.UUCP> Subject: Re: failure of TM I want to thank Bill Poser for taking the time to respond at length to my earlier defense of Peril Slob's parody. I don't think I missed your point, Bill. Note that I never attacked generative grammar or defended Maurice Gross' paper. I merely said that his paper deserved a response. I do not believe that all generative grammarians avoid discussing issues, but there is a pernicious attitude in the field that generative grammar can afford to rest on its laurels. You yourself seem quite ambivalent about whether or not generativists should ignore criticisms. You bring up many examples of earlier exchanges between generativists and their critics. What you don't seem to recognize is that the debate will never end. And it shouldn't. There is a constant flow of newcomers to the field who need to be exposed to the same old 'tired' arguments. The foe is never vanquished. Jim Higginbothm once put it very nicely to a conference on formal syntax when he pointed out that we are all wrong in the long run. The foundations crumble, and they get replaced. So you need to keep shoring up the foundations. Thanks for pointing out Newmeyer's response to Gross. That is a much better way to handle this matter than to say that the paper doesn't merit a response. Yet you still defend this arrogant nonsense that generative grammarians can ignore frontal attacks published in a major journal like Language. We are not talking about Voprosy Jazykoznanija, but about the linguistic journal with the widest readership in the world. Look at your wording: >Back in the days when generative grammar was new and >it was necessary to win people over, it was necessary to defend generative >grammar, and this was done. Now that generative grammar is by far the dominant >school among theoreticians (though arguably not among all who call themselves >linguists) it isn't necessary. Maybe this is arrogant, maybe not. You don't >see physicists responding to every crank attack on relativity. Biologists >... >I think that generative grammarians feel that the relevant >issues have already been debated and that now that they have won the field >it isn't worth their while to respond all the time. When new challenges Articles like the Gross paper don't appear in every issue of Language, and someone could surely spend the time to take the editorial board to task for permitting nonsense. Physicists have more respect for their colleagues than to let their journals get away with irresponsible clap. The lack of a response suggests widespread approval and/or the inability to respond. You said that Language should not be taken as an authority. I agree. It should be taken as a forum for discussion. Here is a passage that puzzles me greatly: > Let me add that I don't entirely agree with the strategy of not >replying to criticism. One reason is that it is unfortunate for incorrect >views to spread, even if they have no real intellectual impact. A second >is that some people may honestly not know why what they are saying is silly >and will feel that it is unfair if they do not receive a response. So >I think that it is generally a good idea for people to publish replies to >criticism. On the other hand, I have to agree that it often isn't worth it >and that it is better to get on with real work. Your last sentence seems totally at odds with the rest of the paragraph. You can't have it both ways, you know. In any case, I agree with most of the paragraph, and I would add another reason to disagree with the attitude that criticism can be stonewalled. You can't really defend ideas by refusing to let them be challenged. You end up playing power politics--intellectual king of the hill--and you lose touch with the rationality that allowed your own ideas to gain credence in the first place. I have not tried to defend the Gross article here, although I think that you have sorely misrepresented it in your discussion. Gross did not defend traditional grammar, for example. He only lamented the narrow scope of generative endeavors in comparison to it. But the real issue is not Gross, it is the strange attitude that generative grammar doesn't need a defense. (Actually, you didn't really say this--you seemed to say that it does need a defense, but only when you think it needs a defense, which is to say not often, and surely not in this case.) I don't always agree with the editorial board of Language, but they are not linguistic mountebanks. Gross intended an honest intellectual challenge, and he got the intellectual finger in return. =========== Rick Wojcik rwojcik@boeing.com ------------------------------ Date: Wed, 27 Jan 88 18:25 EST From: Bill Poser <poser@russell.STANFORD.EDU> Subject: Re: failure of TM Rick, I am curious as to how I might have misrepresented Gross, at least on his main points. That would be pretty tough unless you believe that he wrote a misleading abstract for his own paper. As for the one point you mention, that I mis-represent Gross as advocating traditional grammar, I don't think I misrepresented him at all. To begin with, I didn't say exactly that. What I said was that Gross compared generative grammar unfavorably with traditional grammar in claiming that generative grammar did not lead to grammars as comprehensive as traditional ones, and that Gross considers construction of comprehensive grammars a virtue. Both of these points are quite explicit in the body of Gross' paper as well as the abstract. I did not say that Gross actually advocated traditional grammar. The apparent contradiction that Rick sees in my views on whether generative grammarians should respond to criticism is easily resolved. In an ideal world everybody would know all of the literature and would have infinite time in which to reply to everything with which he or she disagreed. Under such circumstances there can be no doubt that it would be best to reply to every criticism. In practice, however, we don't have time to do all that, and so have to be selective. In deciding what to reply to, two criteria come to mind. First, reply when a significant issue is raised, since in this case debating the issue is most likely to lead to advances in knowledge and since the propagation of a dubious view is most likely to set people off on the wrong track. Second, reply when there is danger that failure to reply will have unfortunate political consequences, either in the broader sense of impact on society or in the narrower sense of effects on grants, faculty appointments, and so forth. For the most part, replies to crank literature are not motivated under either criterion. In the particular case of Gross' paper, I would classify it as marginal. I think that its argument is so confused that it doesn't really require response under the first criterion, though it is better than Ian Robinson's book, for example. Under the second criterion, however, it arguably does. Although _Language_ is not one of the top theoretical journals, it is widely read and so articles in it can have a big impact. So if I had been more advanced in my career in 1980 (and of course, if I thought then as I do now) I might well have replied to it. I note, however, that whether or not someone should have replied does not bear on what inferences can be drawn from failure to reply. It is not legitimate to infer approval or inability to reply. (By the way, this raises a pet peeve of mine, which is that some journals, _Language_ among them, do not accept letters to the editor or other short communications. In the case of something like Gross' paper, this is probably the most suitable response, and of course if it is possible to present a short reply someone is more likely to take the trouble to write one.) There is one major issue on which I was disappointed to see no response. I denied that in general generative grammarians had a greater tendency than anyone else to refuse to reply to criticism. Where are all the examples of the criticism to which generative grammarians have failed to respond? Is Gross's paper the only example? I maintain that the serious issues are being discussed all the time. One example I gave in my previous message was the connectionist assault on generative views of rules and representations in morphology, to which Pinker and Prince have replied. You seem to think that it was only in the early days that generative grammarians defended their ideas, but even the examples I already gave, including this one belie that. Fritz Newmeyer's book (1983) hardly dates back to the beginnings. Even Georgia Green's review of Ian Robinson's book (1977) is not that long ago. Recent examples are easily multiplied. One example is to be found in a book I have sitting on my desk, entitled _Modularity in Knowledge Representation and Natural Language Understanding_, edited by Jay L. Garfield (MIT Press, 1987). Modularity, and associated issues of the autonomy of grammar, syntax, etc., is controversial and associated with generative grammar. Here's a book containing both attacks on this position (e.g. the chapter entitled "Against Modularity" by Marslen-Wilson and Tyler) and defenses by such people as Fodor, Higginbotham, and Frazier. Here's another example. The status of statistical generalizations about surface word order has been a bone of contention between main-stream generative grammarians and Greenbergian typologists. _Language_ 60.55-69 (1984) contains a paper by Peter Coopmans, "Surface Word-Order Typology and Universal Grammar" attacking the Greenbergian approach. Here's still another. Langendoen & Postal's book _The Vastness of Natural Languages_ argues that natural languages cannot even in principle be described by generative grammars because they are not recursively enumerable. _Language_ 62.154-156 (1986) contains a review by Barbara Abbott. Where is the refusal to debate the issues? Let's not get bogged down on the question of under what circumstances a reply is warranted. I agree that ideally one should reply to everything. My point has to do with (a) why, whether rightly or wrongly, people don't always reply; (b) what are reasonable criteria to apply given that one has to allocate scarce time and energy. But that is not the central issue. The central issue is whether it is even true that generative grammarians are worse than other people in failing to reply to criticism and defend their ideas. I have denied that this is true, and so far all we have is the single example of Gross' paper. On what basis do you claim that generative grammarians generally refuse to defend themselves? What makes you think that anybody else is better? Bill ------------------------------ Date: Thu, 28 Jan 88 11:38 EST From: Alan Lovejoy <alan@pdn.UUCP> Subject: Re: failure of TM In article <1860@russell.STANFORD.EDU> poser@russell.UUCP (Bill Poser) writes: > Consider first Gross' paper. In an attempt to give a fair >summary I will quote the abstract of this paper, written by Gross, >in its entirety: > > An attempt to construct a generative grammar of French > with a coverage comparable to that of traditional grammars > has failed. A description has been arrived at in the > course of this work, however; it is much more complex > than expected, and turns out to be entirely taxonomic. > This result calls into question the validity of the > so-called theory of generative grammar. > >In other words, because generative grammarians have thus far not >produced comprehensive generative grammars, the theory must be wrong. >This is a non-sequitur. Generative grammar does not purport to >provide an especially efficient means of constructing grammars. >Generative grammarians have devoted their efforts primarily to >constructing theories, to testing them, and to deep studies of >particular phenomena that they hope will elucidate the nature of >language in general. Since they have not tried to construct >comprehensive grammars and since the theory makes no claim of >efficiency at doing so, how can the fact that generative grammarians >have not constructed such grammars bear on the validity of the theory? There is a fundamental and fatal misunderstanding of just what generative grammar, formal language theory, mathematical linguistics, denotational semantics and semiotics ARE. People tend to see them as theories about the real world instead of a metalanguage in which to express theories about real AND/OR IMAGINARY worlds. The attacks against generative grammar tend to be about as valid as an attack against Euclidean Geometry based on the premise that Einstein discovered that space is curved. Euclidean Geometry is an ABSTRACTION whose "truth" or "validity" have nothing to do with how well it maps onto Einsteinian space-time. Generative grammar is anologous to an algebra. Just because no one can produce equations in the algebra that correctly describe the behaviour of French speakers proves only that the present equations are wrong, not that the algebra is flawed. Physicists cannot write a "grammar" (single set of equations) which describe the behaviour of all known physical objects. Does this prove that Mathematics is bunk? Transformational grammar is analogous to a Calculus. There are many dynamical systems whose behaviour can be described but not predicted with differential equations because no one knows how to solve them. Does this prove that Calculus is bunk? No way. And the fact that a TG has not YET been produced which completely describes any natural language should not be surprising: look how many CENTURIES passed from the invention of calculus to QED theory!!! TG is a YOUNG branch of mathematics. It may be centuries before some applied linguist will be able to use it to completely describe a natural language. --alan@pdn ------------------------------ Date: Fri, 29 Jan 88 08:59 EST From: merrill@iuvax.cs.indiana.edu Subject: Re: failure of TM /* Written 11:38 am Jan 28, 1988 by alan@pdn in iuvax:sci.lang */ Transformational grammar is analogous [sic] to a Calculus. There are many dynamical systems whose behaviour can be described but not predicted with differential equations because no one knows how to solve them. Does this prove that Calculus is bunk? No way. And the fact that a TG has not YET been produced which completely describes any natural language should not be surprising: look how many CENTURIES passed from the invention of calculus to QED theory!!! TG is a YOUNG branch of mathematics. It may be centuries before some applied linguist will be able to use it to completely describe a natural language. /* End of text from iuvax:sci.lang */ There is a fundamental difference between Calculus and TG. Calculus was invented to solve problems that it solved; transformational grammar was created to solve problems that it has failed to solve. To be sure, syntacticians can create grammars for small fragments of the written language, but there is no language---not even Turkish---for which an adequate grammar has been constructed for a large fragment of the written language. No spoken language has been even roughly approximated. Wisely, I suspect, since, like this sentence, spoken language tends to be ungrammatical. The claim that "look how many centuries passed &c" is a traditional dodge, as commonly used in my own field of AI as it is in Linguistics. In either case, the appropriate response is: "if your tools are not yielding interesting results in the fields for which they were designed, you've got the wrong tools." Tools are designed to solve problems, and those which are designed, and then don't work immediately, should be discarded. ------------------------------ Date: Fri, 29 Jan 88 11:55 EST From: Greg Lee <lee@uhccux.UUCP> Subject: Re: failure of TM In article <2132@pdn.UUCP> alan@pdn.UUCP (0000-Alan Lovejoy) writes: +In article <1860@russell.STANFORD.EDU> poser@russell.UUCP (Bill Poser) writes: +>... +>constructing theories, to testing them, and to deep studies of +>... +There is a fundamental and fatal misunderstanding of just what +generative grammar, formal language theory, mathematical linguistics, +denotational semantics and semiotics ARE. People tend to see them +as theories about the real world instead of a metalanguage in which +to express theories about real AND/OR IMAGINARY worlds. +... +Generative grammar is anologous to an algebra. Just because no one can +... What an awful idea. How comforting to a generative grammarian who is unable to find evidence to support his views. Let us solicit the opinion of a mathematician as to whether transformational grammar is worth pursuing for its mathematical interest. Greg, lee@uhccux.uhcc.hawaii.edu ------------------------------ Date: Wed, 27 Jan 88 12:43 EST From: DAVID PESETSKY <PESETSKY@cs.umass.edu> Subject: Gross's article Speaking as a (generative) linguist, it seems to me that the recent discussion about Gross's old paper in Language, and the absence of a published generativist's reply leaves one important point out. Of course, whether someone giggled or not at the paper makes no difference if the work giggled at is of high quality or theoretical importance. The point is that there are papers published, particularly in our young and somewhat inchoate field, to which the appropriate reply would be a few sentences -- and there is no printed forum for such a reply. Perhaps that is where e-mail comes in. Here is one perhaps appropriate reply -- with the caveat that I do not have the paper by Gross at hand: Gross decided to undertake a massive project on the lexicon-syntax interaction at a time when our understanding of either the lexicon or syntax was not at a level to carry it out. In fact, such a project would be only slightly less premature today. Having made this premature attempt, and failed, he pronounced generative grammar a failure in his opening sentence. It's rather as if I decided to travel to another solar system, discovered that it could not be done with present technology, and thereby pronounce engineering, or physics a failure. Or perhaps I decide to produce a full computer simulation of the human being, from biochemistry to gross anatomy; discovering that I cannot do it, I declare biology a failure. It's because of the patent absurdity of such conclusions that the article went without a reply. Sure, his attempt failed -- it was bound to; but who was Gross to decide for generative grammar what the field should be capable of at some given moment. Remember, generative grammar has existed in its present form for quite a short time. We know lots more than we used to (cf. Halle and Higginbotham's reply to Wasow on "Linguistics as a Science" in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory from a year or so back), but a lot less than we hope to. If we had all the answers, we wouldn't be asking any questions, and we are asking lots of them. It seems quite odd to blame a science for not having the answers to certain problems -- even fundamental ones. It's by asking questions and struggling to find answers to them -- yes, even fundamental ones -- that a living field stays alive. David Pesetsky Dept. of Linguistics South College University of Massachusetts Amherst, MA 01003 pesetsk@umass.bitnet ------------------------------ Date: Fri, 29 Jan 88 13:41 EST From: Bruce E. Nevin <bnevin@cch.bbn.com> Subject: the Gospel according to Newmeyer BP> From: Bill Poser <poser@russell.STANFORD.EDU> BP> Subject: Re: failure of TM BP> But what I responded to was not Gross, it was a reference BP> to Gross. In particular, I responded to two points: BP> (a) the appeal to authority of citing Gross and referring to the BP> prestige of the journal in which his paper was published. BP> Saying that the authority is not so authoritative is BP> a perfectly appropriate response to an appeal to authority. BP> It is not I who have refused to discuss ideas. It is a little hard to tell who is responding to whom. I regret that you have evidently taken my reference to the the prestige of _Language_ as an appeal to authority. What I meant by noting the recognition accorded the journal of the Linguistic Society of America was only that the lack of response could not have been because it was printed in some obscure place and therefore overlooked. I did and do inveigh against appeals to authority. The question of perceived standing and circulation of journals is important. _Language has been criticized as being anti-Generativist because it publishes non-Generativist and even on occasion anti-Generativist contributions. (I suppose I could find some references if you question that.) Some of the other journals cited recently in this forum do not. This makes it difficult for alternative perspectives to get a hearing. For an assessment of some aspects of this difficulty and its implications for the health of the field, see Sternberg, Crisis in Linguistic Inquiry, _Forum Linguisticum_ 3.3:189-207 (1973). This journal may be hard to find, of course. I assume that the discussion and advocacy of pluralism in linguistics (interestingly parallel the pluralist/analytical political controversy in philosophy) continues in more recent literature, but I have not seen it because I do not have access to non-"mainstream" (political term) journals. BP> (b) the false inference that failure to reply to Gross in print BP> constitutes a tacit admission of defeat on the part of BP> generative grammarians. Look, Maurice Gross is no dummy. He is not to be compared with creationists in biology, nor are his writings to be compared with "every crank attack on relativity" in physics. His book _Mathematical Models in Linguistics_ (Prentice-Hall 1972) is still both useful and used. His detailed publications coming out of ongoing research in the grammar of French at the LADL and CERIL at the University of Paris VII since the mid 1960s are available for anyone who wants to evaluate "the putatively comprehensive grammars that Gross holds up as the standard". How can it possibly be appropriate to publish no rejoinder in a comparable place? Gross was Chomsky's darling, his hope of further conquests on the Continent, until Gross began pressing harder for ways to produce a real grammar that is actually useful for something (a matter of some concern to computational linguists), and began getting answers to his questions from Chomsky's teacher because Generativists had none. Now, he is an un-person. Only the Party Historian, Newmeyer, has anything to say. And what does Newmeyer have to say? By your account: BP> Newmeyer's main point is that Gross errs BP> in assuming that a generative grammar must account for all of the BP> facts about a particular construction by means of a single rule. BP> He illustrates this assumption of Gross regarding the English Passive BP> construction, then summarizes a modular approach in which different BP> aspects of grammatical theory together provide an account of the Passive. BP> He also points to extragrammatical factors that play a role in determining BP> the acceptability of passive sentences. What Gross is concerned with is not the Passive (though that is the first of four examples), but rather characteristics of the Generative paradigm or programme (Lakatos's term) that make it unworkable. In particular, he is concerned with the Generativist redefinition of data as existing in the metalanguage rather than in the language. (Please read that sentence twice.) In the section in question, 1.1, he points to difficulties with the passive that have been known, yes, since before Chomsky (who learned about them from Harris), and says "the severity of these [difficulties] renders surprising the tenacity put into formalizing it." Because for over thirty years continuing efforts >have< been made to treat it under a single rule or operation, and it >has< continued to be the stock example illustrating what transformations are for the neophyte. And Gross refers to Harris's proposals for the passive as a resultant of combinations of rules that also apply to different constructions, proposals that were soon to be published (in 1982) in section 8.4 of Harris's _Grammar of English on Mathematical Principles_. They are thus integrated in a comprehensive grammar. The "modular" proposals (ah, what a buzzword there!) that Newmeyer puts forward are isolated. We have no idea whether they will fit consistently together with other latest and greatest proposals to make a comprehensive grammar. Generativist linguists are exactly in the position of AI researchers who have made toy systems for somall domains and then discover that they cannot generalize from them to larger domains or general coverage. This is one of Gross's main points. But Newmeyer makes not note of it, but instead provides yet another example as his suggested counterexample regarding the isolated problem of the passive! Now as to synonymy, yes, Chomsky (following Quine, Harris, Bloomfield) rejects it as undefineable. I believe what Gross is referring to here is heuristic practice, not theoretical principle. In practice, when Generative linguists consider paradigms (sets of examples) they frequently refer to differences of meaning to demonstrate that two sentences are derived or do not derived from a common underlying source. Often, this is put in terms of consequences deducible from each sentence, and the claim is sometimes made that two sentences are synonyms iff one may deduce from each the same set of consequences. In any case, his substantive point, which follows immediately upon the passage that Newmeyer excises for ad hominem carping, is that one must proceed, as in any science, with an adequate range of data systematically arranged. He inveighs against the almost exclusive use of anecdotal data in Generativist literature. About this, Newmeyer says nothing. Nor does he say anything about the substantive results of Gross's large-scale, systematic study of distributional facts of French. Instead, he limits himself to the vacuous superciliousness of "It is hard to imagine the source of such a peculiar idea," an almost comical parotting of Chomsky's polemical style. Note that he had no need to "imagine" the source of the idea, the source was set before him in the very article he was allegedly discussing. Gross was referring to some problematic consequences of the the way the competence/performance dichotomy (a very slippery, equivocal concept) is used in Generative theory. The sentence Newmeyer picks out of context immediately follows this quote from Chomsky's 1962 Texas Conference paper: There are in fact exceptions to many of the transformational rules given above, perhaps all. These will have to be separately listed, unless some more general formulation can be found to account for them as well. The discovery of such exceptions is in itself of little interest or importance (although the discovery of an alternative formulation in which the exceptions disappear would be highly important) . . . But discovery of exceptions to grammatical generalizations is of no consequence in itself, except when it leads to an alternative, more comprehensive generalization. It is at this point that Gross says "Under the most favorable interpretation, Chomsky appears to regard the exception to a linguistic rule as a physical scientist might regard an experimental result incompatible with his theory as being caused by some unperceived error in the experimental apparatus." (865) And after the part that Newmeyer quotes, he goes on to say: Certainly a physical scientist who has not explicitly designed an 'experimentum crucis' is reluctant to abandon his theory on the basis of one experimental failure. Nevertheless, it is his responsibility to DEMONSTRATE, either by experimental repetition under better conditions or by an analysis, that the given experimental result inconsistent with his hypothesis is in fact erroneous by reason of experimental error. It will not do to dismiss a sentence acceptable by those competent in a language, when theory suggests it should be unacceptable (or conversely), simply by noting that it is an exception. Of course, any natural language will have exceptions, i.e. special usages; of course, one may not be able to demonstrate at once that each is idiosyncratic; but at the least, one must note all the exceptions, even if one defers their consideration for later study. Discussion of Passive over more than twenty years is a striking example of this methodological error, which consists basically in denying the requirement that relevant linguistic instances be enumerated. [A footnote here describes the derivation proposed by Harris, mentioned above, which avoids the "complex problems of notational formalization" {reference to Chomsky 1975:106-17} that have been >seriously< entertained in Generativist literature.--BN] It will be hard for the specialist in a natural science to believe that such investigations have never been undertaken for questions of English syntax. Traditional grammarians did not construct syntactic inventories either. [I believe your claim was that Gross was holding Traditional grammar up as a standard for comparison? It is difficult to see how you could hold this view if you had read past the abstract.--BN] But today we know they did not possess methods and motivations that might have enabled them to succeed. Transformational methods [NB, not Generative methods--BN] made this form of research possible; and for practically all problems of syntax, accumulating data appears to be at least as necessary as it is for Passive. Since new insights into the nature of syntactic phenomena are likely to arise from systematic exploration with the aid of a dictionary, it is all the more surprising that GG has ignored this aspect of linguistics. Accumulating data is obviously not an aim in itself. But in all natural sciences it is a fundamental activity, a necessary condition for evaluating the generality of phenomena. Such a concept of generality or of importance of facts is totally absent from GG, where sentences acquire significance only with respect to formalism. In GG, a linguistic example appears to be significant only if it allows one to choose between competing theories. . . . I quote this extensively to show that Gross is making non-trivial and substantive claims that Newmeyer simply ignores with a bit of hand-waving--precisely the criticism others here have recently laid against Generative linguistics. But it served its intended purpose, because the party faithful can read and quote Newmeyer and know that they don't have to bother to read and understand Gross. This appears to be what you have done: BP> In an attempt to give a fair BP> summary I will quote the abstract of this paper, written by Gross Internal evidence, such as your misconstrual of the status Gross accords to Traditional grammar, suggests that you read only the abstract and Newmeyer's critique. Please correct me if I am wrong by addressing some of the substantive issues in the article. BP> In sum, Gross's paper badly misrepresents the claims of generative grammar BP> and proposes totally inappropriate tests of its validity. That's why BP> it wasn't taken very seriously at MIT. You go on to say: BP> Let me now respond to the claim that what arouses the BP> ire of anti-generative people is the putative tendency of generative BP> grammarians to dismiss all criticism and refuse to discuss the issues. BP> I don't really believe that this is true in general, and I would be BP> most interested to hear of examples. Thank you for providing two. I must say I was not surprised at the shallowness of Newmeyer's supposed critique of Gross. I had previously been exposed to the shoddy scholarship of his _Linguistic Theory In America_ (1980). Just a couple of howlers from the early pages of the first chapter: The dominant intellectual force in the United States from the 1930s to the 1960s was empiricism. (3) This statement is just incredible. He uses the term "empiricist" as a mere epithet for rhetorical effect, faithfully following Chomsky's claim that he, the Rationalist, split with Harris, the Empiricist (he is none), over their irreconcilable philosophical differences. An example of Newmeyer's distortion for rhetorical effect is his use of the relatively unknown and unused name "Logical Empiricists" for the philosophical school much more generally known as Logical Positivists, and his implication without quite saying that Harris, Bloch, and the rest were all Logical Positivists (patent nonsense). The goal of structural linguistics was to "discover" a grammar by performing a set of operations on a corpus of data. (6) The "taxonomicist" quest for a discovery procedure is another part of the standard mythology of Generative linguistics. Newmeyer says he rejects the contrary view of Hymes and Fought ("American Structuralism", in _Current Trends in Linguistics_, the volume on Linguistic Historiography (1975), pp. 904-1176), as indeed he must since the facts of history contradict the myth. Consider for example the testimony of Harris (1951), which Newmeyer like everyone else takes to be the locus classicus of the "taxonomic" straw man: These procedures are not a plan for obtaining data or for field work. . . . The procedures also do not constitute a necessary laboratory schedule in the sense that each procedure should be completed before the next is entered upon. In practice, linguists take unnumbered shortcuts and intuitive or heuristic guesses, and keep many problems about a particular language before them at the same time: . . . The chief usefulness of the precedures listed below is therefore as a reminder in the course of the original research, and as a form for checking or presenting the results, where it may be desirable to make sure that all the information called for in these procedures has been validly obtained. Harris, _Methods in Structural Linguistics_, 1-2 (1951, ms completed January 1947) Elsewhere (I cannot find the quote), Newmeyer makes the stock claim that "taxonomic" linguistics cannot account for novel utterances and so cannot account for the "generative" capacities (one of the many senses of that highly equivocal term!) of native speakers. Contrast again the following from our locus classicus: The work of analysis leads right up to the statements which enable anyone to synthesize or predict utterances in the language. The elements form a deductive system with axiomatically defined initial elements and with theorems concerning the relations between them. The final theorems would indicate the structure of the utterances of the language in terms of the preceding parts of the system. Harris, 1951, 372-3 Please note that Harris's current operator-argument grammar, which claims to attain this aim, is a product of continuous development from, and not revolutionary refutation of, structural methods. From the point of view of linguistics as a science, the Generativist revolution was unnecessary, although from the point of view of politics it has had its own sufficiency. Finally, a couple of closing observations. You say: BP> Generative grammar does not purport to BP> provide an especially efficient means of constructing grammars. BP> . . . they have not tried to construct BP> comprehensive grammars and . . . the theory makes no claim of BP> efficiency at doing so From the point of view of someone who wants to apply linguistics to practical ends, people like computational linguists and Maurice Gross, this makes Generative Linguistics pretty useless. Generative Grammar by your own admission then does fail to serve such ends. It doesn't matter that Generative linguists have not taken up such aims (is that your claim, really?) and can therefore be said technically not to have "failed". Such sophistry does nothing for a computer scientist with problems to solve. If Generative Linguistics does not address those problems, then the computer scientists will re-invent linguistics, and Generative Linguistics will be just plain irrelevant to the enterprise. This is in fact what we see around us today. BP> In sum, I do not think that it is true that generative grammarians BP> have, in general, ignored the serious challenges to their approach. BP> They have ignored criticism that was plainly silly, and they have ignored BP> repetitions of criticisms involving issues they consider to have been BP> settled long ago or to reflect irreconcilable philosophical differences. Gross is not silly, and he is raising new issues. Even if he is raising issues that you think were "settled long ago", are you saying that issues cannot be reopened in light of new evidence (of which he presents an abundance)? And are you saying that "irreconcilable philosophical difficulties" are on a par with these two criteria for ignoring criticism? Then inter-paradigmatic discussion is not merely difficult, it is foreclosed, and by your choice. More than once I have seen a linguist of a non-Generativist persuasion rise at the conclusion of a talk by a Generativist to comment that the knotty problems just presented by the speaker simply do not arise at all in their alternative paradigm. Gross points to several such phenomena in his discussions of the Passive, Raising, Relativization, and so-called French "aspirated h" in phonology. The affordance of "parallax" between two perspectives can be extremely useful in disclosing phenomena that are mere artifacts of the notation or other conventions used by one or the other paradigm. Another example is the X-bar notation taken by Chomsky from Harris's 1946 paper. The problem that it addresses simply does not arise with center-and-adjunct grammar (string grammar). This was the motivation for Joshi's exploration of grammars with mixed types of rules, and currently of tree-adjunction grammars (TAGs). But the neo-Talmudism (Michael Kac's father proposed the term) of Generative linguistics seems to preclude this kind of exploration and discourse. In consequence, the field is becoming increasingly insular, provincial, and irrelevant. The drying up of funding and the shrivelling or merger of linguistics departments is one overt consequence that we have seen for a number of years. Bruce Nevin bn@cch.bbn.com <usual_disclaimer> ------------------------------ Date: Sat, 30 Jan 88 00:54 EST From: rolandi <rolandi@gollum.Columbia.NCR.COM> Subject: the imaginary worlds of grammarians Regarding the following dribble.... >+There is a fundamental and fatal misunderstanding of just what >+generative grammar, formal language theory, mathematical linguistics, >+denotational semantics and semiotics ARE. People tend to see them >+as theories about the real world instead of a metalanguage in which >+to express theories about real AND/OR IMAGINARY worlds. >+... >What an awful idea. How comforting to a generative grammarian who >is unable to find evidence to support his views. Let us solicit the >opinion of a mathematician as to whether transformational grammar >is worth pursuing for its mathematical interest. >Greg, lee@uhccux.uhcc.hawaii.edu Yo! Greg! Give it up! Why would you want to question the meanderings of this grammarian! What do you want? Words with referents? Statements that are, in some small way, related to facts? My God man, do you fancy a theory about the real world? Don't challenge this guy. Let the philosopher sleep! He may be dreaming that you and I exist! We, and the language we use to describe our existence, may only exist in the metalanguage of his imaginary world! An imaginary world entirely defined in terms of his meaningless terminology!! Walk softly man! walter rolandi rolandi@gollum.UUCP () NCR Advanced Systems, Columbia, SC u.s.carolina dept. of psychology and linguistics ------------------------------ End of NL-KR Digest *******************