[comp.doc.techreports] sigart.4

leff@smu.UUCP (Laurence Leff) (11/28/88)

Subject:  AI-Related Dissertations from SIGART No. 104, part 3 of 3

        The following is a list of dissertation titles and
        abstracts related to Artificial Intelligence taken
        taken from the Dissertation Abstracts International
        (DAI) database.  The list is assembled by Susanne
        Humphrey and myself and is published in the SIGART
        Newsletter (that list doesn't include the abstracts).
        The dissertation titles and abstracts contained here
        are published with the permission of University Microfilms
        International, publishers of the DAI database.  University
        Microfilms  has granted permission for this list to be
        redistributed electronically and for extracts and
        hardcopies to be made of it, provided that this notice
        is included and provided that the list is not sold.

	Copies of the dissertations may be obtained by
	addressing your request to:

		University Microfilms International
                Dissertation Copies
                Post Office Box 1764
		Ann Arbor, Michigan 48106

	or by telephoning (toll-free) 1-800-521-3042
        (except for Michigan, Hawaii, and Alaska).
        In Canada: 1-800-268-6090.


From SIGART Newsletter No. 104
File 3 of 3
Library Science to Social Work
--------------------------------------------------------------------

AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-16512.
AU DALRYMPLE, PRUDENCE WARD.
IN The University of Wisconsin - Madison Ph.D 1987, 326 pages.
TI RETRIEVAL BY REFORMULATION IN TWO LIBRARY CATALOGS: TOWARD A
   COGNITIVE MODEL OF SEARCHING BEHAVIOR.
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Library Science.
AB The study was designed to test hypotheses derived from a
   psychological theory of remembering. An analogy between patterns
   of retrieval from human long-term memory and information retrieval
   from bibliographic databases was proposed. The model, known as
   retrieval by reformulation, was first articulated by Williams and
   Tou in 1982. The setting for the research was the public catalog
   at the University of Wisconsin-Madison, where a substantial
   portion of the library's bibliographic records is available in two
   formats, a card catalog and an online catalog. Forty university
   students in two groups were randomly assigned to the two catalogs
   and completed a series of five searches on specified topics. It
   was hypothesized that the two searching environments were
   sufficiently different, particularly in the degree and kind of
   feedback provided to searchers, to allow observation of
   differences on four classes of variables: search outcome, attitude
   toward the search experience and assessment of search results,
   perseverance, and number of reformulations. Findings indicated
   that greater perseverance and more frequent query reformulations
   were associated with the online searching context. Larger
   retrieval sets and more favorable search assessments were
   associated with the card catalog context. No significant
   differences were found between groups on the attitudinal measures;
   however, initial steps were taken toward identifying three
   effective constructs: "affability," "frustration," and
   "expectation." In order to observe the cognitive processes used in
   searching, subjects were asked to "think aloud" while they
   searched. Transcripts of these verbal protocols were used to
   identify reformulations and to further operationalize the
   theoretical construct "reformulation." Observations were made
   regarding the utility of protocol analysis in information
   retrieval research. Additional post hoc analyses included overlap
   of sets of retrieved items and investigation of variance
   associated with the use of test questions.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-23441.
AU BARLOW, JUDITH ANN.
IN University of Colorado at Boulder D.B. 1987, 175 pages.
TI INTERACTIVE DECISION FRAMEWORKS FOR MULTICRITERIA OPTIMIZATION.
SO DAI v48(08), SecB.
DE Operations Research.
AB Multiple Criteria Decision Making (MCDM) models allow for the
   incorporation of numerous incommensurable goals and objectives as
   criteria for decision analysis. A new interactive decision
   framework for use in solving MCDM problems is presented in this
   dissertation. This method is an interactive form of compromise
   programming which is especially appropriate for problems which are
   best evaluated from multiple risk perspectives and in cases where
   numerous decision making perspectives serve as the multiple
   criteria in the model.

   The problem of selecting the most appropriate MCDM model for a
   particular application is itself a MCDM problem. Because the
   majority of decision making criteria used in selecting the most
   appropriate MCDM model include qualitative heuristics, traditional
   mathematical MCDM methods are not appropriate for the solution of
   these problems. An expert system, the Multiple Criteria Decision
   Making Model Adviser presented in this dissertation, was developed
   to advise the practitioner in selecting the most appropriate MCDM
   method for the solution of a particular MCDM problem.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-18423.
AU LESH, STEPHEN AUGUST.
IN Duke University Ph.D 1986, 330 pages.
TI AN EVIDENTIAL THEORY APPROACH TO JUDGMENT-BASED DECISION-MAKING.
SO DAI v48(05), SecB, pp1501.
DE Operations Research.
AB In both decision analysis and artificial intelligence, the
   problems of representation and manipulation of information for
   prediction of likelihoods are often strikingly similar.
   Particularly in highly subjective or highly uncertain domains, the
   decision process is more sensitive to decision maker judgments
   about likelihood information than in domains captured
   satisfactorily by objective likelihoods. The mathematical theory
   of evidence, applied as an underlying theory for evidential
   reasoning expert systems in artificial intelligence, also
   possesses attractive representation and manipulation properties as
   an underlying theory for judgment-based decision analyses.
   Interval expected utilities resulting from such an evidential
   analysis are decisive only in action choice for nonoverlapping
   intervals. For overlapping intervals, a clear choice is not
   indicated given the nature of the supporting evidence. However, in
   an irreducible ignorance situation where a decision must
   nevertheless be made, an innovative evidential interval-based
   decision index is proposed that explicitly represents evidential
   ignorance as well as decision maker preferences for coping with
   that ignorance. A model for ignorance preferences permits decisive
   choice under overlapping intervals and irreducible ignorance. The
   evidential approach is illustrated by application to an
   environmental management problem: forest prescribed burn
   execution. Extension of the method to utilities as well as
   likelihoods is discussed. The evidential decision making approach
   provides (1) an explicit representation of evidential ignorance,
   (2) an index of conflict among bodies of evidence to guide
   learning, and (3) a decision index for otherwise inconclusive
   decision situations. For decision problems characterized by large
   degrees of uncertainty, incompleteness, or imprecision or highly
   subjective inputs based on a number of sources of varying
   reliability and relevance (i.e., judgment-based decision making),
   an evidential theory approach to decision making may provide a
   useful alternative to one based on probability theory.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-23145.
AU BAR-ON, DORIT.
IN University of California, Los Angeles Ph.D 1987, 439 pages.
TI INDETERMINACY OF TRANSLATION: THEORY AND PRACTICE (QUINE).
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Philosophy.
AB To an ordinary translator, the idea that there are too many
   perfect translation schemes between any two languages would come
   as a surprise. Quine's thesis of the indeterminacy of translation
   expresses just this idea. It implies that most of the 'implicit
   canons' actual translators use in their assessment of translations
   lack objective status. My dissertation is an attempt to present a
   systematic challenge to Quine's view of language (and mind) and to
   support the idea that one could develop an objective theory of
   translation which is also faithful to actual translation
   practices.

   I expose a non-superficial similarity between external-world
   scepticism and Quine's meaning-scepticism, and deploy against
   Quine an objection which closely resembles his own objection to
   external-world scepticism. I then develop a new interpretation of
   Quine's reasoning, according to which denying objective status to
   intuitive 'meanings' is Quine's way of avoiding a sceptical
   problem about what other people 'really' mean.

   I argue that the intelligibility of Quine's meaning-scepticism
   turns on an implicit contrast between the perspective of the
   theorist of language and the perspective of the user of language.
   Quine's defense of his scepticism features a theorist of language
   trying to probe an alien language-- a 'radical translator' -- who
   reasons that her own judgments as a language user lack objective
   status.

   I take issue with the use Quine makes of the above contrast. I
   first argue that understanding the goal of radical translators
   requires knowing what is to be expected of an adequate translation
   scheme. Since this is something we learn from experience with
   existing translation schemes, I offer a pre-theoretic description
   of the practice of translation between known languages. I show how
   ordinary translators' assessments of the quality of given
   translations derive from systematic judgments they make as
   language-users. It is these sorts of judgments that guide actual
   radical translators in ruling out bizarre alternative translations
   of the kind Quine entertains in defending his scepticism. A proper
   theoretical account of radical translation, I conclude, must begin
   with-- and include-- the perspective of the radical translator as
   a language-user.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-23148.
AU BRAUN, DAVID MARTIN.
IN University of California, Los Angeles Ph.D 1987, 304 pages.
TI CONTENT AND PSYCHOLOGICAL EXPLANATION.
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Philosophy.
AB Thought experiments show that people who are physically identical
   but have different environments can have mental states with
   different contents. But many philosophers think that physically
   identical people must also be psychologically identical. They
   therefore believe these thought experiments show that differences
   in mental state content do not necessarily mark genuine
   psychological differences, but are instead merely fallible signs
   of psychological differences. They conclude that content
   attributions do not have a fundamental role to play in
   psychological explanation.

   I argue that persons whose mental states have different contents
   are also psychologically different. Their mental states differ in
   their psychologically important causal powers. Their mental states
   tend to have different environmental causes and effects and tend
   to have causes and effects with different intentional properties,
   and these differences are psychologically important. So to
   distinguish mental states by their contents is to distinguish them
   by psychologically important properties. I also develop a theory
   of content suitable for psychological explanation. The theory
   appears able to distinguish between any two mental states that are
   psychologically different, even in puzzle cases like Kripke's
   famous example of Pierre.

   Some critics of content contend that for psychological purposes we
   need a new notion of content, narrow content, that supervenes on
   physiology. I critically examine several different theories of
   narrow content. I divide the theories into two kinds: "indexical"
   theories (modeled after Kaplan's theory of indexicals) and
   phenomenological theories. Some of these kinds of content do not
   supervene on physiology. Other kinds of narrow "content" are
   actually not kinds of content, or have other problems that make
   them practically unsuitable for psychological theory.

   I conclude that psychology needs broad content (i.e., content as
   we ordinarily conceive it), and that it needs no other notion of
   content.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-23150.
AU CHRISTENSEN, DAVID PHIROZE.
IN University of California, Los Angeles Ph.D 1987, 231 pages.
TI EMPIRICAL EQUIVALENCE AND SKEPTICAL METHODOLOGY: THE CASE OF THE
   SWITCHED WORDS.
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Philosophy.
AB In this dissertation, I study the strategy of giving semantical
   replies to skeptical puzzles. I concentrate on a very simple kind
   of puzzle, which seems to invite--and perhaps even
   require--semantical responses.

   Skeptical problems of this kind, which I call "switched-words"
   problems, are based on alternative hypotheses about the world
   which are structurally very similar to our standard hypotheses;
   for example, it has been asked how we can justify choosing our
   standard physical theory over an alternative hypothesis formulated
   by taking the standard theory and intersubstituting 'electron' and
   'molecule' at every occurrence. Switched-words skeptical puzzles
   are peculiarly resistant to anti-skeptical arguments based on
   non-semantical considerations such as simplicity, ontological
   economy, or explanatory power; however, they leave one feeling
   that there must be some easy semantical way of answering the
   skeptic. Thus they offer a way to isolate and study semantical
   anti-skepticism in an environment where it should thrive.

   In the first Chapter, I examine, and reject, the classical
   semantical response of saying that the alternative theory simply
   restates the standard theory in a different notation. The second
   Chapter is devoted to a more precise statement of the
   switched-words problems, and involves a methodological analysis of
   just what anti-skeptical premises a skeptic must accept. In
   Chapter Three, I examine another recent semantical answer to
   switched-words skepticism, finding a modified version of it to be
   applicable, though in a limited number of cases.

   In the fourth Chapter, I develop a general form for giving
   semantical answers to switched-words skeptics, which has the
   last-studied answer as a special case. This general strategy is
   independent of any particular semantical theory; it explains the
   general failure of switched-words skepticism by reference to a
   general feature of any plausible semantical theory. It also
   explains why, in certain cases, the switched-words skeptic is
   correct (a possibility discounted by others who have written on
   this issue). Studying this strategy in Chapter Five reveals that
   while it is important--even necessary--in replying to certain
   kinds of skepticism, it cannot offer us an anti-skeptical panacea.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-17624.
AU DREBUSHENKO, DAVID WILLIAM.
IN The Ohio State University Ph.D 1987, 185 pages.
TI ABSTRACTION AND THE 'ESSE' IS 'PERCIPI' THESIS (BERKELEY, LOCKE).
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1221.
DE Philosophy.
AB The dissertation is divided into two parts. In Part One, Locke's
   theory of abstract general ideas is introduced and it is explained
   how it is to be used in giving an account of how certain common
   nouns refer. In the second chapter, Berkeley's attack on the
   theory of abstract ideas is described. In the third chapter, a
   defense of the doctrine proposed by J. L. Mackie is considered. It
   is argued that this fails as it stands, but the chapter goes on to
   suggest how Mackie's account can be revised so as to overcome
   these shortcomings. In Part Two, some aspects of current thinking
   concerning one of Berkeley's central arguments for Esse is Percipi
   is discussed. In the chapter following this discussion, another
   interpretation of the argument for Esse is Percipi is proposed and
   an attempt is made to explain how this interpretation overcomes
   some of the problems connected with other interpretations. In the
   last chapter, an attempt is made to show that there is a direct
   connection between the doctrine of abstract ideas and the Esse is
   Percipi thesis. More exactly, it is argued that if there are
   abstract ideas, then the Esse is Percipi thesis is false.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-19990.
AU GLEB, GARY TIMOTHY.
IN University of California, Los Angeles Ph.D 1986, 481 pages.
TI JUSTIFICATION AND SCEPTICISM ABOUT THE EXTERNAL WORLD (DESCARTES,
   EPISTEMOLOGY).
SO DAI v48(06), SecA, pp1468.
DE Philosophy.
AB I investigate the extent to which Descartes's sceptical arguments
   in the Meditations show that, given a traditional view of
   justification, we cannot have justified beliefs in the external
   world. On this traditional view, knowledge is essentially
   justified true belief, and many beliefs are justified only if they
   are backed by reasons. Consequently, one's justified beliefs are
   thought to form a system: an inverted pyramid, resting on
   foundational beliefs, or a 'raft', held together by coherence.

   To illuminate this view, I contrast it with the 'reliabilist' view
   of knowledge. Within this alternative view, the demand for
   justification by reasons is largely replaced by a demand that a
   modal relation holds between a knower's belief and his
   environment. If this relation holds, then the belief is likely to
   be true.

   I contend that these views really agree on this point, since a
   reason for belief, on the traditional view, also involves a
   relation with this character. Then, starting from some ideas due
   to Bonjour, I argue that the 'reliabilist' view does not
   appreciate that epistemic activity is rational activity directed
   at a goal--the acquisition of true beliefs. Consequently,
   epistemic agents are normally obligated to have means to this
   goal, namely, reasons for belief. In making my argument, I develop
   an original account of epistemic possibility and doubt.

   I then examine Descartes's sceptical arguments. If one accepts the
   traditional view, I argue, one holds expectations about
   justification that amount to constraints on acceptable systems of
   justified belief. One is that a system is acceptable only if the
   beliefs in it are likely to be true. Another is that a system is
   acceptable only if it is sensitive to truth: that is, if the world
   were different, the system could 'shift' towards the truth. But
   Descartes's Dream and Demon Arguments seem to show that these
   constraints, together with others, form an inconsistent set.

   I discuss several strategies against these arguments, and show
   that each rejects or radically revises some of the constraints. I
   end by proposing a strategy, based on a transcendental argument,
   that does neither.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-20611.
AU GOETZ, STEWART CALVIN.
IN University of Notre Dame Ph.D 1987, 231 pages.
TI A NONCAUSAL THEORY OF AGENCY.
SO DAI v48(06), SecA, pp1468.
DE Philosophy.
AB My dissertation consists of two main parts. In the first part, I
   begin by assuming the plausibility of the libertarian thesis that
   agents sometimes could have done otherwise than they did given the
   very same history of the world. In light of this assumption, I
   undertake to develop a model of agency which does not employ the
   concept of agent-causation. My agency theory is developed in three
   main stages: (i) I suggest that any agency theory must satisfy
   four desiderata: (1) It must adequately account for the freedom
   and responsibility of human agents. (2) It must provide an
   adequate answer to the question of what distinguishes human
   actions from mere happenings. (3) It must adequately account for
   the epistemological fact that human agents have an immediate and
   nonobservational awareness of their actions. (4) It should have
   the support of a respectable philosophical tradition. I argue that
   agent-causation provides a theory of agency which fails adequately
   to satisfy these four desiderata. (ii) I claim both that human
   actions are uncaused exercisings by agents of their powers and
   that human agents typically act for reasons. (iii) I maintain that
   the central issue dividing agency theorists and nonagency
   theorists is whether reasons for performing actions cause the
   latter. I maintain that the sense of 'because' in 'I did x
   because...' is not causal in nature, but teleological.

   Having developed my model of agency, in the second part of my
   dissertation I investigate what are some of the paradigmatic
   actions human agents perform. I claim that bodily actions, such as
   moving an arm, are psychological in nature. Essential to my
   argument is the concept of a body-image. A normal agent 'feels' as
   if she is present in her physical arm. The way a normal agent
   feels is revealed in the case of a phantom limb. The subject of a
   phantom arm feels as if her amputated physical arm is still there
   and she can move while feeling armishly. I maintain that the
   bodily action of moving an arm is the agent's movement as a
   psychological arm-image of her physical arm, whether the physical
   arm is present or not.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-17431.
AU HIX, HARVEY LEE.
IN The University of Texas at Austin Ph.D 1987, 207 pages.
TI "WHAT PART OB YU IZ DEH POEM??": AUTHORSHIP AND AUTHORITY IN
   INTERPRETATION (MICHEL FOUCAULT, ALEXANDER NEHAMAS, ROLAND BARTHES,
   WILLIAM GASS).
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1222.
DE Philosophy.
AB It is often assumed that the correct meaning of a philosophical or
   literary work is the meaning the writer intended to convey. Some
   modern critics have reacted against that assumption by saying that
   there is no correct meaning of a work because the work's meaning
   is to each reader what that reader takes the meaning to be. In
   this dissertation, I argue for a via media: I try to show that
   both the writer and the reader have creative roles in determining
   the meaning of a text.

   In the first chapter, I examine the debate between Michael
   Foucault and Alexander Nehamas on what an author is. I argue
   against Foucault that the difference between the writer of a work
   and the 'author-character' in it does not imply that a reader
   should be indifferent to the writer. I argue against Nehamas that
   the connection between the writer and the author-character is not
   capable of disclosing to the reader a unique, correct meaning.

   In chapter two, I consider the debate between Roland Barthes and
   William Gass on the death of the author. I argue against Barthes
   that the reader does not wholly determine the meaning of the text,
   and against Gass that the writer does not wholly determine the
   meaning of the text.

   In chapter three, I analyze the creative act to show that it
   consists of at least five roles (which I name the ore, arche,
   archive, artisan, and artifact). I show that these five roles need
   not be filled by a single individual, and that the assignment of
   the creative roles influences the meaning of a text. For instance,
   if God has the role of arche, the meaning of the Bible is
   different than its meaning if humans have that role.

   In the fourth chapter, I show how variations from the "standard"
   creative act may occur. I classify these variations into three
   types of 'displacement' (a variation in which an extra step is
   added to the creative process) and two types of 'multiplication'
   (a variation in which more than one item or individual performs a
   role in creation), and show how each of the variations influences
   interpretation.

   In chapter five, I evaluate the notion of the "implied author" in
   the work of Wayne C. Booth and Jenefer M. Robinson. I argue
   against them that the implied author is not created exclusively by
   the writer, and that there is more than one implied author at work
   in a given text.

   In the final chapter, I identify three kinds of 'implied authors':
   the narrator, a character within the work, the singular proxy, the
   'author' postulated by the reader to account for the features of
   the individual work in question, and the synoptic proxy, the
   'author' postulated to account for the features of the corpus to
   which the work belongs. I classify several kinds of relationship
   which may hold between these 'implied authors' and show how the
   relationship that holds in a given work influences the
   interpretation of that work.


AN This item is not available from University Microfilms International
   ADG05-60732.
AU JACOBSEN, ROCKNEY ALAN.
IN University of Alberta (Canada) Ph.D 1987.
TI PERCEPTION AND JUDGEMENT.
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1222.
DE Philosophy.
AB Beginning with a criticism of the adequacy of a causal framework
   for discussing human action and with a minimal explication of a
   teleological framework, an account of the acts subordinated to
   language learning and use is developed and defended. This account
   emphasizes the nature of the semantic conventions of a language
   and the role of a community in establishing and maintaining those
   conventions.

   The teleological framework is brought to bear to explain the
   intensional character of indirect discourse. Well known
   isomorphisms between indirect discourse and belief reports then
   make it possible to extend the account of acts of speech to
   explain belief acquisition, thus completing an account of the
   nature of judgement. The result of employing teleological notions
   is that our judgements are no longer viewed as mental artifacts,
   or products of mental activity, which serve to represent the
   world. Our judgements about the world, both what we say and what
   we think, are, rather, the achievements we reach through the
   coordinated exercise of skills acquired in a community setting.

   Success in an inquiry depends upon skill in judging, but it also
   requires an opportunity adequate for bringing us to knowledge or
   justified belief. Perception provides that opportunity. An account
   of perception is defended which emphasizes its role in providing
   opportunities for taking discriminatory action towards the world
   of public particulars. A consequence of the accounts of belief
   acquisition and language learning is that perception is
   non-epistemic.

   The theories of judgement and perception presented appear to
   create special difficulties for understanding how perception
   contributes towards our arriving at opinions which we are
   justified in holding to be true. The conclusion defended, contrary
   to traditional empiricist theories of knowledge, is that
   perception does not contribute towards the evaluation of
   judgements. The role of perception in inquiry is remote and
   causal; it makes it possible for us to make judgements about the
   world, but does not contribute to our getting things right.
   Skepticism is blocked, and our beliefs are justified, by the work
   of linguistic communities in preserving semantic conventions for
   speech and thought. Perception belongs to the natural world, but
   the adjudication of contrary opinions and the conduct of inquiries
   belongs to the social world.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-21418.
AU KOEHN, MARK ALLEN.
IN The University of Iowa Ph.D 1987, 166 pages.
TI THE LINGUISTIC LIMITATION (EPISTEMOLOGY, JUSTIFICATION).
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Philosophy.
AB There is often thought to be an inconsistency involved in the
   holding of a sceptical view with regard to knowledge, especially
   if one's scepticism approaches the level of a universal
   scepticism. It is, of course, obvious that if I deny that we ever
   know anything then I cannot claim to know such a fact, and, more
   generally, it is equally clear that a sceptical doctrine cannot
   have a higher epistemic status than the highest epistemic status
   allowed by the doctrine itself. In my case, then, since my
   scepticism is complete, it seems that the propositions making up
   my position must be devoid of epistemic value. However, there are
   other reasons for making assertions than simply the belief that
   one knows them to be true or even that one has reason to believe
   that they are true. One of the goals of my argument is to show
   what follows from a particular set of assumptions, a set of
   assumptions that is quite generally accepted. I am, in part,
   attempting to make clear the consequences of certain views. At
   various levels this project is an investigation into the nature of
   the relations among various propositions and sets of propositions,
   an attempt to show the connections between certain epistemological
   doctrines and metaphysical views, between the ongoing rounds of
   'example counter-example' epistemology and the fundamental
   assumptions the epistemologists engaged in it, between absolute
   justification and weaker forms of justification, between views
   about the nature of thought, language and rationality and the
   consequences such views have for what can consistently be held
   within the fields of epistemology and metaphysics, between changes
   in the concepts of 'truth', 'justification', and 'certainty' and
   the consequences for the meaning and significance of actualized
   knowledge claims. Thus, an epistemological view whose statements
   are by the decree of that very view without epistemic value may
   provide the context for discussion and understanding of more
   general topics.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-20033.
AU KOONS, ROBERT CHARLES.
IN University of California, Los Angeles Ph.D 1987, 213 pages.
TI ANALOGUES OF THE LIAR PARADOX IN SYSTEMS OF EPISTEMIC LOGIC
   REPRESENTING META-MATHEMATICAL REASONING AND STRATEGIC RATIONALITY
   IN NON-COOPERATIVE GAMES.
SO DAI v48(06), SecA, pp1469.
DE Philosophy.
AB The ancient puzzle of the Liar (a sentence which says, in effect,
   "I am untrue") was shown by Tarski to be a genuine paradox or
   antinomy. I show, analogously, that certain puzzles of
   contemporary game theory are genuinely paradoxical, i.e., certain
   very plausible principles of rationality, which are in fact
   presupposed by game theorists, are inconsistent as naively
   formulated.

   I use Godel theory to construct three versions of this new
   paradox, in which the role of 'true' in the Liar paradox is
   played, respectively, by 'provable', 'self-evident', and
   'justifiable'. I also construct in modal operator logic a paradox
   involving reflexive empirical reasoning. Unlike the paradox of the
   Liar, the paradox of reflexive reasoning does not depend on
   self-reference.

   I consider various solutions to the Liar paradox and evaluate how
   well these solutions cope with the paradox of reflexive reasoning.
   I then formalize the solution to the paradoxes which I favor: the
   indexical-hierarchical approach, first sketched out by Charles
   Parsons and Tyler Burge. In this solution, occurrences of the
   predicate 'true' (and, analogously, of 'self-evident' and
   'justified') in sentence-tokens are contextually relativized to
   levels of a hierarchy. Drawing also on some brief remarks of
   Bertrand Russell and Charles Parsons, I develop an account of the
   kind of schematic generality (or type-ambiguity) needed for this
   theory to be statable.

   Finally, I demonstrate that the principles shown to be paradoxical
   are in fact presupposed by contemporary game theorists in their
   reliance on the notion of common knowledge or, more precisely,
   mutual belief. I create novel analyses of and corresponding
   solutions to several recalcitrant puzzles within game theory,
   including the "chain-store paradox".


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-23037.
AU LANGHOLM, TORE.
IN Stanford University Ph.D 1987, 174 pages.
TI PARTIALITY, TRUTH AND PERSISTENCE (SEMANTICS).
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Philosophy.
AB In recent years, semantical partiality has emerged as an important
   explanatory concept in philosophical logic as well as in the study
   of natural language semantics. Despite the many applications,
   however, a number of mathematically intriguing questions
   associated with this concept have received only very limited
   attention.

   The present dissertation aims to present a systematic study of
   certain types of partiality in the area of basic model theory. Two
   types of issues are given special attention: Introducing partially
   defined models, there are many ways to generalize the classical
   truth definition for sentences of a simple first order language
   relative to standard, complete models. Different interpretations
   of the formal framework motivate conflicting truth definitions
   between language and partial models: A partial model can be taken
   to represent a part of the world, or a partial information set.
   The truth of a sentence can be supported directly by a part of the
   world, but can also follow indirectly from an information set.
   These notions are related, and the relation motivates a comparison
   between various weaker and stronger alternative truth definitions.
   Results are obtained about the extent to which these truth
   definitions differ, and a number of characterization results are
   deduced.

   Among other conditions that are not expressible in the framework
   of standard, complete model theory, a condition of monotonicity or
   persistence of truth relative to partial models is argued to
   follow under both the given interpretations of the formal
   framework. The final chapter investigates the relation between
   such conditions and expressibility properties in general. These
   discussions culminate with a combined Lindstrom and persistence
   characterization theorem.


AN This item is not available from University Microfilms International
   ADG05-60893.
AU MALPAS, JEFFERY EDWARD.
IN The Australian National University Ph.D 1986.
TI AGREEMENT AND INTERPRETATION.
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Philosophy.
AB This dissertation is an examination of certain ideas arising out
   of the philosophy of Donald Davidson and specifically out of his
   conception of 'radical interpretation'. The aim of the work is
   only partly one of exegesis; primarily it attempts to develop the
   idea of 'interpretative holism' implicit in Davidson's work and to
   develop also the implications which flow from that holism. The
   notion of interpretative holism is a development on the
   Davidsonian idea of the interdependence of meaning and belief--an
   interdependence which sets the essential problem of radical
   interpretation--but it also encompasses the other Davidsonian
   marriage of truth with meaning. This emphasis on interpretative
   holism and the particular way in which the notion is developed in
   the dissertation brings with it an orientation more towards
   hermeneutic theories of interpretation than to traditional
   philosophy of language. The first part of the work lays out the
   basic account of Davidsonian radical interpretation with respect
   to its Quinean background and as it is developed through
   Davidson's own work. Here the basic ideas of holism, charity and
   indeterminacy are set out. The second part takes up Davidson's
   application of these ideas to the problems of conceptual
   relativism and epistemological scepticism; the question of the
   transcendental and verificationist status of Davidson's argument
   on these matters is also discussed. The third and final part looks
   at the Davidsonian position in the context of Putnam's distinction
   between metaphysical and 'internal' realisms and looks more
   closely at the conception of truth implicit in interpretative
   holism.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-17689.
AU METZLER, THEODORE ALBERT.
IN The Ohio State University Ph.D 1987, 216 pages.
TI A MODEL OF INTERACTING VISUAL AND VERBAL COMPONENTS IN HUMAN THOUGHT.
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1223.
DE Philosophy.
AB The problem addressed in this dissertation is the problem of
   explaining interaction between visual and verbal components of
   human thought. The fundamental strategy adopted in this work for
   solution of the problem consists of treating both visual and
   verbal modes of thinking in terms of a common formalism that
   describes plausible information processing operations of the human
   brain.

   In Chapter I basic elements of the problem are identified through
   critical examination of Western philosophic history. The resulting
   composite definition of the problem challenges us to explain how
   visual components of human thought interact with verbal components
   to support comprehension of certain words that are used with
   general application, as well as comprehension of combinations of
   such words in sentences and larger units of discourse. Although
   major Western philosophers are shown to have engaged elements of
   this problem repeatedly--over a period of approximately two
   thousand years--various deficiencies in each of their efforts
   indicate that we are addressing an abiding, important, and
   unresolved difficulty.

   In Chapter II and Chapter III a review of contemporary scientific
   resources is employed to further refine formulation of the problem
   and to identify guidelines for a modern "cognitive science"
   approach to its solution. In particular, Chapter II introduces
   relevant evidence obtained by contemporary experimental
   psychologists, and Chapter III provides complementary
   neuroanatomic and neuropsychological information.

   In Chapter IV a general system design for a formal explanatory
   model is proposed, showing linkage among functional components of
   verbal and visual information processing subsystems, and relating
   these components to the structure of the human brain. The basic
   processing units of this model are represented as associative
   matrix memory modules, and the mathematical resources of linear
   algebra are employed to describe the operations they perform.
   After its elementary features have been explained, the model is
   applied to the problem originally defined in Chapter I.

   In Chapter V the proposed model is discussed with respect to the
   work of Western philosophers examined in Chapter I, and with
   respect to future research projects that it may be expected to
   generate.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-17810.
AU PECCHIONI, FRANK.
IN Indiana University Ph.D 1987, 274 pages.
TI META-LANGUAGE AND OBJECT CALCULUS: A CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK FOR
   CARNAP'S 'LOGICAL SYNTAX' (GODEL).
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1224.
DE Philosophy.
AB By developing some recent ideas on the late nineteenth and early
   twentieth century history of logic, this dissertation lays a
   foundation for re-examining the major product of Carnap's early
   philosophical career.

   The pioneering work of Gottlob Frege is the prime example of logic
   as language. According to this view, a purely formal meaning is
   intrinsic to logic and plays a significant role in the conduct of
   inference. Moreover, this intrinsic meaning renders logic
   self-justifying. Currently dominant attitudes adhere more closely
   to logic as calculus. On this view, logic is an empty formalism to
   which an extrinsic meaning may be loosely attached. The
   justification of the system consists in showing it sound and
   complete under a set-theoretically characterized range of
   interpretations.

   The success of this latter view is primarily due to its
   association, first established in Godel's completeness proof, with
   a quite distinct position which we may call meta-linguism. On this
   view, which came to prominence in the work of David Hilbert,
   language is a proper subject for cognitive study. Carnap defended
   this position against one he found in Wittgenstein's work, a
   position we may call extra-linguism. He has therefore been seen as
   ascribing also to the associated calculus view.

   A close examination of certain seminal works of Frege and Hilbert
   shows the compatability of meta-linguism with the language view
   and provides an opening for a reappraisal of Carnap's work. In
   particular, his emphasis on a formal calculus can be seen as only
   a tactic in his argument against extra-linguism, and the language
   view emerges as a significant element in his implicit semantics.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-23068.
AU PEFEROEN, LUDOVIC.
IN Stanford University Ph.D 1987, 179 pages.
TI THE VARIETIES OF THINKING: RYLEAN REFLECTIONS ON THOUGHT AND
   INTELLIGENCE.
SO DAI v48(07), SecA.
DE Philosophy.
AB Ryle, in The Concept of Mind and in his later papers, has
   formulated views on the notions of thinking and intelligence. In
   the first part of the thesis I argue that Ryle's dispositional and
   adverbial account of intelligence is mistaken. I provide an
   analysis of the notion of intelligence that shows it to be related
   to the notion of intention. Ryle's position is vindicated,
   however, in that in calling an act intelligent we are not implying
   that it is the outcome of a process of thinking.

   In a second part I address Ryle's views on thinking. I argue that
   Ryle's adverbial account of thinking is mistaken, but that another
   thesis of Ryle, that thinking is heterogeneous, is correct. I
   review six different forms of thinking and show that they do not
   share any property except the property of being intentional
   episodes. This shows that almost any thesis that historically has
   been held about thinking is false. The analysis of the different
   forms of thinking, moreover, provides a precise formulation and
   defense of Ryle's claim that thinking is not sui generis, but that
   there is a conceptual relation between the various forms of
   thinking and human capacities or skills other than thinking.
   Finally, I argue that thinking is not a form of computation and
   that thinking a thought, contrary to what certain philosophers
   have held, can be a genuine action on the part of the agent.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-20970.
AU ROBERTS, MARK STEVEN.
IN University of Dallas Ph.D 1987, 264 pages.
TI THE ETERNAL EXISTENCE OF TRUE PROPOSITIONS.
SO DAI v48(06), SecA, pp1469.
DE Philosophy.
AB One central issue concerning the relationship between truth and
   time is the mode of being of true propositions. In order to
   understand what mode of being they have one must recognize that a
   proposition is different from any type of mental act whose content
   is a proposition such as an act of judging or doubting.
   Propositions are also different from declarative sentences used to
   express propositions. Moreover, propositions are different from
   states of affairs, the referents of propositions.

   Within the copula of each proposition is a syncategorematic
   positing-concept. Its function is to posit the existence of a
   state of affairs. This is the "claim to truth" made by each
   proposition, and is independent of the asserting of a proposition
   through an act of judging. Proposition are true when there is a
   correspondence between a proposition and an existing state of
   affairs. Truth is a property of a proposition itself and not the
   actual correspondence.

   True propositions are existentially independent of the mental acts
   of persons for two or more persons can think the identical truth.
   Also, there are logical relationships among true propositions
   which obtain although only some of these true propositions have
   been thought. For instance, the contrapositive of each true
   proposition must be true even though the contrapositive
   proposition is not also thought. Furthermore, because of their
   unity and universality true propositions cannot be characterized
   in terms of when and where they came into existence or how long
   they existed. These features of true propositions cannot be
   explained by granting merely the existence of states of affairs,
   or merely the existence of possible true propositions.

   Thus, all true (and false) propositions exist eternally and are
   immutable. However, some eternally true propositions still refer
   to temporallly-existing states of affairs. Nevertheless, they are
   immutable due to the necessary presence of a temporal modality.

   Furthermore, eternally true propositions are not identical to
   necessary truths. The former can be either necessarily true or
   contingently true.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-18768.
AU SKIPPER, ROBERT BOYD.
IN Rice University Ph.D 1987, 286 pages.
TI A CAUSAL THEORY OF 'ABOUT'.
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1224.
DE Philosophy.
AB Whenever we make a claim about a fictional entity, we seem to
   embroil ourselves in familiar problems of reference. This
   appearance is misleading, because what a sentence is about bears a
   greater resemblance to a Fregean sense than to a reference. All
   previous attempts to define 'about' consist of two approaches: (1)
   "metalinguistic" theories of 'about', proposed by Ryle and Carnap,
   which fail to counterexamples wherein transparent contexts
   generate paradoxical consequences; and (2) "semantic" theories of
   'about' proposed by Putnam and by Goodman, which fail to
   counterexamples wherein no term refers to that which the sentence
   is about.

   An untried alternative is to replace 'S is about k ' with 'S is
   about k for person p '. Clearly, such a definition need not
   confine itself to sentences, but may apply to works of art as
   well. A detailed examination of how one actually goes about
   arguing to an audience that some work of art W is about some
   topic, yields a definition that approximates normal usage, yet
   avoids many problematic notions, such as 'beliefs', 'ideas', and
   'intentional states'. Necessary and sufficient truth conditions
   for 'W is about k for p at time T' turn out to include as major
   elements (1) a causal chain leading from W to a set of "explicit
   thoughts" and dispositions, and (2) the lack of an "aesthetic
   environment" which excludes W.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-13178.
AU THOMADSEN, NANCY SWEET.
IN The University of Wisconsin - Madison Ph.D 1987, 181 pages.
TI OPTIMAL ACTS AND OPTIMAL CONSEQUENCES: ON SOME LIMITATIONS OF
   PRACTICAL REASONING.
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1224.
DE Philosophy.
AB In this work I claim that practical reasoning aims at determining
   acts that would be all in all optimal (best) to perform. This
   claim is taken to characterize practical reasoning in the same way
   that the claim that theoretical reasoning aims at determining true
   propositions characterizes theoretical reasoning. It is, in other
   words, not directly a claim about rationality. Rationality is a
   characteristic of beliefs and choices, rather than of propositions
   or, directly, of acts.

   A characterization of what it is for an act to be all in all
   optimal is developed. A particular act, to be performed by a
   particular agent, is all in all optimal only if it is one of the
   best acts that agent could perform, relative to all the facts, all
   evaluative factors and all the act's alternatives. Only acts which
   can be the subject of practical thinking are admitted as practical
   alternatives.

   Since it is here assumed that the value of an act is determined by
   the value of its consequences, it may seem obvious that an optimal
   act is an act which would have optimal consequences. This,
   however, need not be the case. Practical reasoning essentially
   involves the comparison of possible alternatives, some of which
   are not actually performed. Non-performed alternative acts, it
   will be argued, are vague. Therefore, each such act will be
   associated not with a single set of consequences it would have,
   but rather with a set of equally possible alternative outcomes it
   might have. I argue that there is no way to evaluate possible acts
   so that optimal acts must be acts associated exclusively with
   optimal outcomes. The fact that optimal acts may be acts that
   would have less than optimal consequences is attributed neither to
   human epistemological shortcomings, nor to physical indeterminism.
   It is instead attributed to human behavioral limitations, and to
   the apparently ineliminable vagueness associated with possible
   acts.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-19264.
AU PERERA, A. G. UNIL.
IN University of Pittsburgh Ph.D 1987, 113 pages.
TI INJECTION MODE DEVICES (IMDS) FOR INFRARED DETECTION AND NEURAL
   NETWORK EMULATION.
SO DAI v48(06), SecB, pp1732.
DE Physics, Solid State.
AB Spontaneous pulsing has been observed in circuits containing
   cryogenically cooled silicon p-i-n (p$\sp{+}$-n-n$\sp{+}$) diodes
   under dc forward bias. The intensity of infrared radiation
   incident on the diodes and the bias voltage controls the pulse
   rate with no appreciable effect on the shape or size of the
   pulses. The substantial voltage, current, and power output
   eliminates the need for on-chip or off-chip amplifiers. The
   spectral response of such a detector as measured from 22 to
   32$\mu$m with a liquid-helium-cooled monochromator is reported.
   The response is modulated by a multiple internal reflection
   interference pattern. The interference pattern and the origin of
   optical absorption are analyzed. A strong similarity is noted
   between observed properties and the nearly universal means of
   coding of visual information by animal photoreceptors and neural
   networks. Infrared analogs of neural color coding and color vision
   are proposed.

   Time intervals T$\sb{\rm n}$ between successive pulses in spike
   trains with durations up to 30 hours were analyzed as a function
   of n. Temporal patterns depend on bias voltage and are
   characterized by symmetric sets of Farey fraction frequencies
   associated with remarkably narrow peaks in power spectra.
   Resolution permitted identification of 115 of the 129 Farey
   fractions with period $\le$ 40. A rule involving fractions
   appearing in this system and other nonlinear systems is proposed.

   Detector concepts are expanded to incorporate the nonlinear
   dynamics concept of mode locking, which reduces fluctuations in
   detector output without a corresponding reduction in detector
   responsivity, showing minimum resolvable temperatures of 0.01K.

   Simulation of neuron transient phenomena by electronic processes
   in semiconductors is discussed from the point of view of hardware
   for new approaches to electronic processing of information which
   parallel the means by which information is processed in
   intelligent organisms. The typical speed of the observed
   transients has been slow by the standards of electronic switching
   in computers. New results for such transients show much faster
   switching times. Development of this hardware basis is pursued
   through exploratory work on circuits which exhibit some basic
   features of biological neural networks. The features discussed
   include action potentials, refractory periods, excitation,
   inhibition, summation over synaptic inputs, synaptic weights,
   temporal integration, memory, network connectivity modification
   based on experience, pacemaker activity, firing thresholds,
   coupling to sensors with graded signal outputs and the dependence
   of firing rate on input current.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-20594.
AU O'DONOHUE, WILLIAM THOMAS.
IN State University of New York at Stony Brook Ph.D 1986, 151
   pages.
TI THE MEANING AND DEFINITION OF PSYCHOLOGICAL TERMS: A BEHAVIORAL
   APPROACH.
SO DAI v48(06), SecB, pp1817.
DE Psychology, Clinical.
AB The purpose of the present investigation is to develop and employ
   a method of defining psychological terms. To this end, the major
   philosophical views regarding meaning are critically reviewed. The
   approach adopted here--experimental semantics--is most heavily
   influenced by radical behaviorism, but also adopts some of the
   views of ordinary language philosophy, logical positivism and
   operationalism. This approach views language and linguistic units
   as human behavior that can potentially be analyzed in terms of
   their functional relationships with antecedent and consequential
   environmental events. Certain antecedent stimulus conditions that
   systematically influence the probability of the use of a word are
   viewed as giving the word's meaning. This method, then, is used to
   analyze the meaning of the words "prejudice" and "alcoholic".
   General descriptions of the antecedent stimulus conditions found
   functionally related to the use of these words are provided and
   are argued to provide comprise an important part of the lexical
   definitions of these words.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-20055.
AU COOKE, NANCY MARIE.
IN New Mexico State University Ph.D 1987, 135 pages.
TI THE ELICITATION OF UNITS OF KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIONS: ENHANCING
   EMPIRICALLY DERIVED SEMANTIC NETWORKS.
SO DAI v48(06), SecB, pp1831.
DE Psychology, Experimental.
AB The notion that associations of units of knowledge underlie memory
   has been pervasive throughout many psychological paradigms and is
   especially prevalent in current semantic network theories. Units
   of knowledge have been represented in semantic networks as nodes
   and associations between units have been represented as links
   between nodes. Unlike previous associational theories, semantic
   network theories have attributed meaning to associations through
   the use of links labeled with particular relations. Unfortunately,
   there have been as many different types of units and relations
   proposed as semantic network models. Attempts to address these
   variations have been made through the development of semantic
   network formalisms. An alternate approach is through the empirical
   generation of networks using algorithms such as Pathfinder.
   Semantic networks derived from human judgments can be used to
   verify the psychological meaningfulness of intuitively derived
   networks. In addition, the networks have some useful applications
   as knowledge elicitation tools. However, there are limitations
   inherent in the Pathfinder methodology that must be overcome
   before it can be successfully applied. The research discussed in
   this paper addressed two limitations that are also particularly
   relevant to the historical issues of units of knowledge and
   associations. More specifically, the problems of identifying the
   critical units of domain knowledge to be represented by nodes and
   of interpreting or labeling links in the resulting networks were
   investigated.

   In the first two studies units of knowledge were elicited from
   experts in the domains of driving and flight maneuvers. The
   elicitation tasks that were used included the listing of concepts,
   steps, or chapter headings, and the extraction of main ideas from
   an interview. The elicitation techniques differed in terms of the
   quantity of ideas elicited, as well as the type of knowledge that
   was elicited. A second series of studies addressed the link
   interpretation issue using relations in a set of common concepts
   and a set of programming concepts. Subjects either sorted linked
   pairs into groups having the same meaning or labeled links with
   the appropriate relation. Links were ultimately classified using
   cluster analysis techniques. Results indicated that the clusters
   were meaningful and that the link types represented by each
   cluster corresponded to an independently derived taxonomy of link
   types. In general, the techniques investigated in this paper
   represent steps toward the formalization of aspects of the
   Pathfinder methodology that are critical to its application as a
   knowledge elicitation tool and as a tool for validating
   intuitively derived semantic networks.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-20392.
AU GLUCK, MARK ALAN.
IN Stanford University Ph.D 1987, 75 pages.
TI FROM CONDITIONING TO CATEGORIZATION: AN ADAPTIVE NETWORK MODEL.
SO DAI v48(06), SecB, pp1832.
DE Psychology, Experimental.
AB We used adaptive network theory to extend the Rescorla-Wagner
   model of associative learning to phenomena of human learning and
   judgment. In three experiments, subjects learned to categorize
   hypothetical patients with particular symptom patterns as having
   certain diseases. When one disease is far more likely than
   another, the model predicts that subjects will substantially
   overestimate the diagnosticity of the more valid symptom for the
   Rare disease. The results of Experiment 1 and 2 provided clear
   support for this prediction in contradistinction to predictions
   from probability matching, exemplar retrieval, or simple prototype
   learning models. Experiment 3 contrasted the adaptive network
   model to one predicting pattern-probability matching when patients
   always had four symptoms (chosen from four opponent pairs) rather
   than the presence/absence of each of four symptoms, as in
   Experiment 1. The results again supported the Rescorla-Wagner
   learning rule as embedded within an adaptive network model.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-22407.
AU KLUSMAN, PATRICIA M.
IN The University of Nebraska - Lincoln Ph.D 1987, 98 pages.
TI BOOTSTRAPPING: THE EFFECTS OF FEEDBACK IN AN OBSTETRIC DECISION
   CONTEXT.
SO DAI v48(07), SecB.
DE Psychology, Experimental.
AB The purpose of the present study was to investigate the effects of
   feedback on bootstrapped decisions in a natural setting. Ten
   obstetric nurses from St. Elizabeth Community Health Center and
   ten graduate students enrolled in the Psychology Department at the
   University of Nebraska served as expert and novice decision
   makers, respectively. A correlational analysis provided veridical
   rankings for each of 41 community attitude survey items'
   relationship to hospitalization length. To obtain subjective
   rankings, both experts and novices rated the importance of the
   survey items to the criterion. Based on the veridical and
   subjective rankings, the experimenter then prepared obstetric
   profiles from 12 randomly selected surveys. In a split-plot design
   both experts and novices were randomly selected to one of two
   feedback conditions. Subjects' task during the judgment phase of
   the study was to predict the number of days obstetric patients
   were hospitalized for the delivery of their babies on the basis of
   eight cues. Half of the subjects received outcome feedback after
   each of their predictions, while the remaining half received no
   feedback information. Least squares regression weights were used
   to construct subjects' response systems (e.g. bootstrapped models)
   and the environmental system (e.g. optimal linear model). Using
   the lens model approach, the results were that feedback produced
   significant expertise differences in subjects' bootstrapped
   judgments (p $\approx$.05), in the incremental validity of the
   model over human judgments (p $<$.05) and in subjects' response
   matching (p $\approx$.05). On each of these measures, feedback had
   a detrimental effect on novices' performance, while having
   virtually no effect on experts' performance. Edgell's hypothesis
   that professional decision makers may obtain "blinders" in
   processing information was supported. Implications of these
   findings to other professional decision making contexts were
   discussed.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-17482.
AU MCDONALD, KAREN JUNE.
IN The University of Texas at Austin Ph.D 1987, 221 pages.
TI A DISTRIBUTED MEMORY MODEL OF PRIMING AND SEMANTIC DISTANCE CONTEXT
   EFFECTS IN A CATEGORIZATION DECISION TASK.
SO DAI v48(05), SecB, pp1536.
DE Psychology, Experimental.
AB One task which is often used in cognitive research is a
   categorization decision task. In a categorization decision
   experiment, a possible instance (e.g., rose or cedar) and a
   category (e.g., flower) are presented to a subject who must decide
   whether or not the possible instance belongs to the category.

   When a propositional network model is used to describe what occurs
   in the mind during categorization decision tasks, reaction times
   are presumed to be related to the semantic distance between
   concepts. Decision reaction times depend on the number of possible
   choices in the system and the distances between nodes which must
   be searched.

   In the present research, a different metaphor is used. An analogue
   model using the ideas of habituation and sensitization and the
   information theory idea of signal detection is used to explain the
   relative speed of reaction times for different decisions. This
   model has similarities with distributed memory - matrix models
   which have been used for computer simulations of various mental
   processes.

   The results of the research indicate the need for an interactive
   and transformational representation model. Reaction time effects
   are demonstrated not only for different kinds of word pairs but
   for consecutive word pairs and within and between series of word
   pairs. These effects are consistent with an interactive and
   transformational model of mind but not with a propositional
   network model.

   Furthermore, despite the usefulness of propositional network
   models for Artificial Intelligence purposes and for psychological
   simulations of many kinds of thought processes, the distributed
   memory - matrix model appears to be a better model of mind than
   propositional network models for at least two reasons. First, the
   distributed memory - matrix model appears to be a better candidate
   for an interactive and transformational model of mind. Second, the
   distributed memory - matrix model is more congruent with simple
   models of brain functioning.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-11922.
AU PEREZ-COFFIE, JORGE.
IN De Paul University Ph.D 1986, 74 pages.
TI NAIVE REASONING: STRUCTURES AND PROCESSES.
SO DAI v48(05), SecB, pp1536.
DE Psychology, Experimental.
AB The process of understanding and completing analogies and
   metaphors can be thought of as the result of the subjects' use of
   specific structures and processes. The purpose of this study was
   to determine which structures and processes mediate performance in
   analogical and metaphorical reasoning tasks. In the practice phase
   of the experiment, the subjects in the Analogies and Metaphors
   groups were asked to explain analogies and metaphors,
   respectively. In the testing phase, the subjects were asked to
   complete both analogies and metaphors. A group not having a prior
   practice session was included as the Control group. The analysis
   revealed that subjects tended to use a relatively small number of
   structures and processes to explain analogies and metaphors. In
   addition, a regression analysis revealed that subjects'
   correctness scores can be predicted above chance fluctuations
   using as independent variables the mean frequencies of the
   subjects' preferred structures and processes, and the mean number
   of interconnections used by each subject. The results were
   discussed in terms of their applicability to the study of
   information processing models of reasoning.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-19266.
AU ROTH, CHRISTOPHER MICHAEL.
IN University of Pittsburgh Ph.D 1987, 742 pages.
TI NAIVE PHYSICS: A STUDY OF QUALITATIVE KNOWLEDGE AND REASONING AND
   ITS ROLE IN SOLVING NUMERICAL PROBLEMS IN MECHANICS.
SO DAI v48(06), SecB, pp1833.
DE Psychology, Experimental.
AB This research explores the content of naive qualitative knowledge
   and reasoning and its use to represent numerical problems.
   Previous studies of misconceptions about mechanics demonstrate
   that novices can provide qualitative analyses of phenomena and
   often hold erroneous beliefs. In contrast, studies of numerical
   problem solving in mechanics have shown that novices differ from
   experts in not formulating qualitative analyses of a problem but
   do possess valid, if incomplete, knowledge. The initial premise of
   the dissertation research was that the incompatible findings
   across studies of problem solving were due to using an
   insufficient methodology. The research describes a more powerful
   method and its application to these issues. Generally, the method
   employed a wide range of situations and applied subtractive logic
   and formal modeling to develop details about a novice's
   qualitative knowledge that were then used to account for solutions
   to numerical problems. The main findings about qualitative
   knowledge and reasoning were (1) novices possessed articulated
   beliefs; (2) those beliefs exhibited some degree of localized
   generality; (3) novice knowledge was a mix of correct, incomplete,
   and invalid propositions; and (4) most errors were attributable to
   using defective knowledge rather than invalid reasoning. These
   findings, although not entirely novel, are placed on a firm
   empirical foundation through use of the method. The main findings
   about numerical problem solving were: (1) novices used qualitative
   knowledge to represent and solve numerical problems; and (2)
   novices used forward search strategies under certain conditions,
   suggesting that direction of search was a function of experience,
   not expertise. Several findings cut across the kinds of problem
   solving: (1) novices possessed alternative forms of some concepts
   that were not necessarily informationally or computationally
   equivalent; (2) novices did not hold all beliefs with equal
   conviction; (3) relationships varied in the amount of information
   they conveyed, resulting in levels of knowledge intermediate to
   the qualitative and quantitative; and (4) in order for a
   relationship to enter into reasoning, it must be expressible at a
   level of information at least comparable to that embodied in other
   participating knowledge components. Finally, an important feature
   of the dissertation is a description of the method at a level of
   generality permitting extension to other domains.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-24203.
AU STASZEWSKI, JAMES JOHN.
IN Cornell University Ph.D 1987, 125 pages.
TI THE PSYCHOLOGICAL REALITY OF RETRIEVAL STRUCTURES: AN INVESTIGATION
   OF EXPERT KNOWLEDGE.
SO DAI v48(07), SecB.
DE Psychology, Experimental.
AB This research investigates memory mechanisms called retrieval
   structures and their relation to expert skills. Theoretically,
   retrieval structures enhance skilled performance by enabling
   experts to efficiently encode and retrieve large amounts of
   information in long-term memory (LTM).

   Hypotheses about retrieval structure organization, the loci of
   their effects, and their functional properties were derived from
   Chase & Ericsson's (1982) description of these mechanisms and
   tested by having an exceptional mnemonist (DD) memorize and
   retrieve long random digit lists under varied conditions.

   Retrieval structure organization was studied by analyzing pauses
   in DD's serial recall of 100+ digit lists. A detailed structural
   hypothesis predicted the temporal pattern observed. The ability of
   a process-model of retrieval structure operation to predict this
   temporal pattern further supports the hypothesized underlying
   memory architecture.

   Predictions regarding the loci of retrieval structure effects were
   tested by measuring (a) DD's encoding times for individual digits
   of 25-, 50-, and 75-digit lists and (b) the pauses in his
   subsequent serial recall. Correlational analyses show that a
   common temporal structure characterizes DD's encoding and recall
   of lists. The ability of length-specific variants of a general
   retrieval structure model to fit these temporal patterns confirms
   that retrieval structures mediate both DD's encoding and retrieval
   of lists.

   Two key properties of retrieval structures were studied using a
   memory scanning task. After memorizing a rapidly presented
   50-digit list, DD then received list probes to which he responded
   by naming targets that either preceded or followed the probe in
   the list. Analyses of response latencies and verbal reports
   confirmed DD's ability to directly access information encoded via
   retrieval structures. Results also support the claim that
   retrieval structures encode ordinal relations in memory.

   Finally, parameter estimates of DD's memory search rate obtained
   by fitting retrieval structure models to serial recall and
   scanning times show that these mechanisms enable DD to access
   information stored in LTM with the speed and accuracy typical of
   novices' short-term memory retrieval.

   These findings argue for the psychological reality of retrieval
   structures and provide insights into what experts know and how
   they use their knowledge to achieve exceptional performance.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-16612.
AU HOFER, PAUL JEFFREY.
IN The Johns Hopkins University Ph.D 1987, 223 pages.
TI COGNITIVE STRATEGIES FOR INTERPRETING LAW.
SO DAI v48(05), SecB, pp1504.
DE Psychology, General.
AB A cognitive analysis of the information and problem-solving
   components needed for legal reasoning is presented, focusing on
   the judicial interpretation of vague legal rules. There are four
   perspectives or roles from which lawyers reason: the philosophic,
   judicial, advisory, and advocatory. The major structural
   components of the law are the conditions and consequences of
   rules, and the purposes of rules. Purposes are divided into
   policies and principles. To evaluate a rule justified on policy
   grounds, we need to analyse the cause-and-effect relation between
   rule and purpose. Evaluating rules justified by principle does not
   require causal reasoning.

   There are two sources of legal rules, legislative enactments and
   judicial opinions. The source can affect the type of reasoning
   used for interpretation. Several cognitive strategies for
   interpreting vague language and deciding if a rule applies to a
   case are modeled. These are the literal, the instrumental, and
   strategies that weight and combine literal and instrumental
   factors. Literal strategies highlight the lexical properties of
   rule conditions, and require that reasoners make category
   membership or similarity judgments. Instrumental strategies
   highlight the purpose of a rule and the causal link between the
   rule and purpose. The strategies correspond to alternative
   theories of jurisprudence.

   A computerized test designed to diagnose which strategy a person
   uses was created and administered to law students. Results
   demonstrate that for most people, ratings of the applicability of
   a rule to a case can be well predicted by two factors: (1) the
   extent to which the facts of a case are subsumed under the
   categorical terms in rule conditions, and (2) how useful applying
   the rule's consequence to the facts of a case would be for
   accomplishing the rule's purpose. Statutes and precedents are
   treated differently by some reasoners. The implications of this
   model, and the computerized assessment, for legal education, legal
   practice, and the development of computer-assisted legal reasoning
   systems are discussed. Our understanding of high-level reasoning
   skills is greatly increased by a cognitive analysis. A model of
   legal reasoning demonstrates how legal and scientific thinking can
   be integrated.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-17865.
AU COBB, NORMAN, HAROLD-, R.
IN University of California, Berkeley D.S. 1986, 234 pages.
TI ANALYSIS OF JUDGEMENT IN PSYCHOSOCIAL AND BEHAVIORAL CASEWORK.
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1317.
DE Social Work.
AB Social workers are becoming aware of the impact of their decisions
   on people's lives. Unfortunately, research on human judgement
   demonstrates how poorly people make decisions. By looking closer
   at the inferential process in making judgements, we can examine
   the inferences social workers make about the importance or
   relevance of client information.

   Psychological decision theory describes the cognitive processes
   decision makers use. Two common judgement heuristics,
   representativeness and availability, are assumed to influence
   decision makers and explain the occurrence of a common judgement
   error called the Fundamental Attribution Error (FAE). FAE is the
   tendency of an observer to overemphasize the internal causes for
   someone's behavior and underemphasize the influence of external
   causes. The representativeness heuristic describes how persons
   make judgements based on the similarity of objects. For example, a
   person observed dancing in the street may be judged to have a
   happy personality. The availability heuristic explains how people
   base judgements on salient or vivid information, e.g. the rather
   unusual sighting of someone dancing on the street may give rise to
   a judgement questioning the dancers mental health status.

   Five psychosocial and five behavioral caseworkers were videotaped
   in assessment interviews with the same actress, acting a
   prescribed client role. The interviews were structured to allow
   the caseworkers the opportunity to think out-loud about the
   client. The transcripts were analyzed for the presence of
   Fundamental Attribution Error and, the implications are discussed
   for the use or misuse of the judgement heuristics. The project
   evaluated each method's potential for unbiased judgements. The
   caseworkers' inferences were evaluated to determine how the
   heuristics were applied. The project documents that psychosocial
   and behavioral caseworkers emphasize different types of client
   data and differentially emphasize the client's problems.
   Implications for social work clinicians are discussed.


AN University Microfilms Order Number ADG87-18645.
AU HAGA, MYRNA PEARL.
IN University of Minnesota Ph.D 1987, 216 pages.
TI A DESCRIPTION OF EXPERT AND NOVICE CLINICAL REASONING IN AN
   ILL-DEFINED PROBLEM AREA.
SO DAI v48(05), SecA, pp1318.
DE Social Work.
AB A process tracing methodology was used to gain access to the
   clinical reasoning skills used by expert and novice social workers
   during the performance of a novel social work task. The major aim
   was to understand what is actually done by an individual as a
   situation is analyzed and evaluated in order to make a response.
   The rationale for the study lies in the assumption that if the
   skill is to be taught, it must first be identified and understood.

   The methodology used verbal protocols to obtain the data from
   three experts and three novices, who "thought aloud" as they
   progressed toward making a recommendation based on a simulated
   case file. The literal translation was used to obtain episode
   representations, which begin and end with a change in problem
   solving activity. Episode representation was then evaluated as to
   the type of process it contains, with the processes being derived
   from the data. The identified processes become the data for
   analysis. The expert and novice responses were contrasted in each
   phase of the study.

   Phase one identified the processes obtained in the subject
   protocols. The findings indicated that expert and novice social
   workers had the same clinical reasoning processes available for
   use in simulated situations.

   Phase two identified quantitative differences in the processes
   used. The amount of time used by each subject in each process was
   computed and differences between groups were found in five of the
   ten processes. Qualitative differences were observed in three of
   the remaining processes. Quantitative differences between subjects
   in the processes used in differing quartiles was the focus of
   phase three. The total time involved in each process per quartile
   was computed, and a quantitative difference between groups was
   observed.

   Phase four concentrated on the amount of data subjects obtained
   prior to making a recommendation. Results demonstrated that
   experts used less data in reaching a decision and that the data
   accessed was of a different type.

   The final phase concerned the formulation of evaluative statements
   and their position in the protocols. The results showed that early
   evaluative statements were used most often by the novice group.


END OF FILE 3 OF 3