RISKS@KL.SRI.COM (RISKS FORUM, Peter G. Neumann -- Coordinator) (12/23/88)
RISKS-LIST: RISKS-FORUM Digest Thursday 22 December 1988 Volume 7 : Issue 98 FORUM ON RISKS TO THE PUBLIC IN COMPUTERS AND RELATED SYSTEMS ACM Committee on Computers and Public Policy, Peter G. Neumann, moderator Contents: The Fetzer Paper in CACM (Brian Randell) Computers in mathematical proof (Dale Worley) Teaching students about responsible use of computers (Jerome H. Saltzer) Responsible use of computers (PGN) ******************************************************************* * HOLIDAY GREETINGS AND BEST WISHES FOR A LOW-RISK NEW YEAR. PGN * ******************************************************************* The RISKS Forum is moderated. Contributions should be relevant, sound, in good taste, objective, coherent, concise, and nonrepetitious. Diversity is welcome. CONTRIBUTIONS to RISKS@CSL.SRI.COM, with relevant, substantive "Subject:" line (otherwise they may be ignored). REQUESTS to RISKS-Request@CSL.SRI.COM. FOR VOL i ISSUE j / ftp kl.sri.com / login anonymous (ANY NONNULL PASSWORD) / get stripe:<risks>risks-i.j ... (OR TRY cd stripe:<risks> / get risks-i.j ... Volume summaries in (i, max j) = (1,46),(2,57),(3,92),(4,97),(5,85),(6,95). ---------------------------------------------------------------------- Date: Thu, 22 Dec 88 12:43:08 WET DST From: Brian Randell <B.Randell@newcastle.ac.uk> Return-Path: B.Randell%newcastle.ac.uk@NSS.Cs.Ucl.AC.UK Subject: The Fetzer Paper in CACM The following message is intended to serve as a response to the comments by Nancy Leveson et al. (in RISKS-7.84) on our original brief message in RISKS-7.61 about Fetzer's paper. It is extracted from a much more detailed statement that will appear in the Communications of the ACM. The furore that the article has aroused in the program verification community has caused us to go back and re-read Fetzer's paper more carefully, to see whether it really deserves the opprobrium which the program verification community has been heaping on it. Part of the problem seems to us to be the (unfortunately justifiable) fear that the paper will be misinterpreted by laymen, particularly those involved in research funding. We have good reason to sympathise with such reactions, given the misunderstandings that arose in some quarters from the Knight and Leveson paper on design diversity. Indeed, both papers demonstrate the care that needs to be taken in assessing how different readerships will react to one's writings. However we now believe that there are also significant philosophical issues underlying the present debate, which is not helped by the terms in which some of the reactions have been couched. [In our CACM paper, we go on and analyze one such issue, that caused by the difference between explanatory and evidential reasoning.] In essence our view is that the dispute has arisen as a discrepancy between the program verification community's view of their practice and objectives on the one hand, and the outside world's view of those objectives on the other. It is in fact a public image problem, and public image is not to be corrected simply by the writing of intemperate letters. We suspect that a major underlying reason for the undesired image is that there has been a good measure of overselling of the concepts. (This is not of course the first occurrence of this practice in computer science, nor will it be the last.) A recent and all too clear example of this overselling can be seen, in the case of hardware verification, by contrasting exaggerated advertising claims for the VIPER microprocessor (e.g. "VIPER is the first commercially available microprocessor with both a formal specification and a proof that the chip conforms to it") with the careful and balanced discussion, in Avra Cohn's report on her (very impressive) work on formal verification of the VIPER `block model', of what was actually proven, and what was out of scope of the proving techniques. (The above advertisement is in fact quoted by Cohn, who rightly goes on to state that "such assertions, taken as assurances of the impossibility of design failure in safety-critical applications, could have catastrophic results".) If our belief that formal verification has been oversold is correct, then articles such as `Program Verification - The Very Idea', misconceived though we now accept it undoubtedly is, might be seen in the longer term as providing a stimulus for a strategy of corrective measures necessary to counter the false sense of security that is, we fear, all too commonly promoted by vendors of verification technology and/or verified programs. Finally, to avoid any misunderstanding as to our own views, let us make it clear that we in no way dispute that program verification can have a significant role to play in the vital task of clarifying specifications and removing design faults. That, however, is not the issue. John Dobson and Brian Randell, Computing Laboratory, University of Newcastle upon Tyne PHONE +44 91 222 7923 ------------------------------ Date: Thu, 22 Dec 88 10:43:19 EST From: worley@compass.UUCP (Dale Worley) Subject: Computers in mathematical proof From: Henry Cox <cox@spock.ee.mcgill.ca> Subject: Supercomputer used to "solve" math problem [ Article about use of computer search to demonstrate the non-existence of a "projective plane of order 10 deleted. -- drw] The RISKS are obvious. The willingness of people to accept a computer's answer on faith (whether at the cash register at the grocery store or in the university environment) remains disturbing. Henry Cox This is replaying a dispute that arose when the Four-Color Problem was solved via computer search -- If no human mind has comprehended the proof, has it truly been proved? In the case of the Four-Color Problem, it is generally believed to be true, since other people (independently) wrote programs to check the solution. However, from a broader perspective, this is ignoring the fact that many published mathematical proofs have significant errors in them, and not infrequently turn out to be "proving" entirely false statements. For instance there is a famous theorem whose proof was 300 pages long, in which 100 or so errors have been found (and corrected). Consider how many errors are probably in the proof of the Simple Group Theorem, which is a compendium of papers by 100 or so mathematicians, totalling about 2000 pages. In cases not involving humans, no one would say "The willingness of people to accept other people's answers on faith remains disturbing" -- after all, we can't re-prove *everything* we read. When computers are involved, often the disturbing change is not that we take *more* on faith, but that it becomes *so obvious* we take things on faith. Similarly, when a human controller screws up and causes a train collision, we consider this an unfortunate accident. When a computer control does the same, we wonder why people would rely on computers... Personally, I'd rather depend on the cash register to do the addition than the minimum-wage clerk operating it. Dale ------------------------------ Date: Thu, 22 Dec 88 15:51:46 EST From: Jerome H. Saltzer <Saltzer@ATHENA.MIT.EDU> Subject: Teaching students about responsible use of computers There has been some discussion in RISKS recently about what action universities might appropriately take to instill a sense of ethics in the use of computers by their students. M.I.T.'s Project Athena provides some 800 networked engineering workstations for undergraduates to use in any way they find helpful to their education. Accordingly, Project Athena has assumed that one of its responsibilities is to open a discussion of ethical use with its user community. The primary action that Project Athena has taken is the publication of a set of principles, a copy of the current version of which is attached. These principles are for the most part general, following M.I.T.'s usual approach of appealing to basic concepts rather than spelling out many detailed rules. There is no claim that publicizing these principles completely solves any problem nor that it completely answers any question, but it does represent one organization's attempt to take a step in the right direction. Some version of these principles has been posted for about four years, and whenever we have an incident serious enough to ask a student to talk to the Director, these principles have provided a very useful starting point for the conversation. Jerry Saltzer ----- ----- ----- ----- ----- ----- ----- ----- ----- ----- ----- Principles Of Responsible Use Of Project Athena Project Athena is M.I.T.'s computing facility for education. It consists of a networked system of workstations and services, and includes communication features that offer many opportunities for members of the M.I.T. community to share information. With that ability to share comes the responsibility to use the system in accordance with M.I.T.'s standards of honesty and personal conduct. Those standards, outlined in the M.I.T. Bulletin under Academic Procedures, call for all members of the community to act in a responsible, ethical, and professional way. This note offers guidelines in applying those standards to use of Project Athena facilities. INTENDED USE The hardware granted to Project Athena, and the software licensed for that hardware, are intended for educational use, broadly construed, by members of the M.I.T. community. Use of Athena resources by anyone outside M.I.T. requires approval of the Provost, and the sale of such use is improper. The use of Athena resources for immediate financial gain is similarly improper. Use of Project Athena's facilities for sponsored research activities that normally would make use of other M.I.T. facilities requires specific authorization of the Director. PRIVACY AND SECURITY The operating systems used by Project Athena encourage sharing of information. Security mechanisms for protecting information from unintended access, from within the system or from the outside, are minimal. These mechanisms, by themselves, are not sufficient for a large community in which protection of individual privacy is as important as sharing. Users must supplement the system's security mechanisms by using the system in a manner that preserves the privacy of others. For example, users should not attempt to gain access to the files or directories of another user without clear authorization from the other user (typically that authorization is expressed by setting file access permissions to allow public or group reading). Nor should users attempt to intercept any network communications, such as electronic mail or user-to-user dialog. A shared program should not secretly collect information about its users. Personal information about individuals, which a user would not normally disseminate, should not be stored or communicated on the system. Examples of such personal information are grades or letters of recommendation. SYSTEM INTEGRITY Actions taken by users intentionally to interfere with or to alter the integrity of the system are out of bounds. Such actions include unauthorized use of accounts, impersonation of other individuals in communications, attempts to capture or crack passwords or encryption, and destruction or alteration of data or programs belonging to other users. Equally unacceptable are intentional efforts to restrict or deny access by legitimate users to the system. INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS Some software and data that reside on the system are owned by users or third parties, and are protected by copyright and other laws, together with licenses and other contractual agreements. Users must abide by these restrictions. Such restrictions may include prohibitions against copying programs or data for use on non-Athena systems or for distribution outside M.I.T., against the resale of data or programs or the use of them for noneducational purposes or for financial gain, and against public disclosure of information about programs (e.g., source code) without the owner's authorization. It is the responsibility of the owner of protected software or data to make any such restrictions known to the user. ------------------------------ Date: Thu, 22 Dec 1988 16:01:42 PST From: Peter Neumann <neumann@csl.sri.com> Subject: Responsible use of computers There are still many would-be contributions in the RISKS pipeline on the general topic of computer misuse. Some reiterate points already made several times before. Others elaborate on relatively minor points. Thus, I have been a more rigorous enforcer of the RISKS guidelines than usual on this topic -- hopefully without unbalancing the representativity of the dialogue. I am grateful to Jerry for providing a general, principled view of part of the problem. The bottom line is that responsibility is of necessity widely distributed. We certainly need better ethics and better laws, and better teaching of their implications. We also need a society that respects them. But our society needs much more that that; those of us who look at the world only from the vantage point of our computers are missing much. (I say this not just in the spirit of the season.) Unfortunately, reality suggests that even the best ethics and laws will be violated by people responding to misplaced incentives (financial or otherwise). (The drug situation and insider trading are two examples that are difficult to combat with ethics and laws alone. They are deep social problems. And hacking can certainly become a social disease!) Thus, we also need computer systems that can enforce security and integrity much more thoroughly, and we need those systems to be administered and used intelligently. (That already may be expecting too much.) But by now it is generally realized that we cannot depend only on computer security controls -- there are just too many ways to break them in the systems that we must use. So, to end the soap-box for this year, security, integrity, software safety and system safety (e.g., in the sense of Nancy Leveson, Avra Cohn, and others) are system-wide (and network-wide) concepts. There are many life-critical or other critical applications in which we must rely on both people and technology (especially computers) to perform properly (i.e., within tolerances); as we have seen in many cases discussed in RISKS, deviations may result in catastrophes that are unacceptable to the affected individuals, if not to society as a whole. This applies to disastrous design flaws, programming errors, acts of God, and many other problems in addition to intentional system misuse. One rotten apple (human or technological) can spoil the barrel. The message for RISKS readers is once again that we must never blindly trust that computers and people will always do the right thing, and that we must plan accordingly. The problems require a comprehensive approach. If the real risks (as opposed to the perceived risks) are too great, then we had better rethink the use of computers in those applications. But let's honestly address the REAL RISKS. Happy holidays! Peter ------------------------------ End of RISKS-FORUM Digest 7.98 ************************ -------