larry@VLSI.JPL.NASA.GOV (10/21/87)
FLAWED/FLAWLESS: I can argue on both sides. FLAWLESS: Quality can only be judged against some standard. Every person has (perhaps only slightly) a different value system, as may even the same person at different times. So what is a flaw to one may be a "feature" to another. (Examples: a follower of Kali may consider torture, death, and corruption holy; a worshipper of the Earth Mother may consider monogamy a sin and infertility a crime.) The only objective standard is survival of the largest number of one's species for the longest time, and even this "standard" is hopelessly flawed(!) by human subjectivity. FLAWED: Nevertheless, humans DO have standards, and not only for made objects like automobiles, that are essential to our survival and happiness. We want lovers who have compatible timing (social, sexual), sensitivity (at least enough not to hog the blankets or too obviously eye the competition), enough intelligence (so we can laugh at the same jokes) but not too much (winning an occasional argument is necessary to our self-esteem), etc. Notice that TOO MUCH intelligence may be considered as bad a flaw as too little. And more FLAWLESS: From an evolutionary standpoint what is a "virtue" in one mileau may become deadly when the environment changes. Performing some mental activity reliably may be of little use when chaos sweeps through our lifeways. THEN divergent thinking--or even simple error--may be more likely to solve problems. A perfect memory (popularly thought to accompany great intelligence) can be a liability, holding one rigidly to standards or knowledge no longer valid. It is also the enemy of abstract/general thought, which depends on forgetting (or ignoring) inessentials. (Indeed, differential forgetting may be one of those great ignored areas of fruitful research.) AI: What does all this have to do with artificial intelligence? Maybe nothing, but I'll invent something. Say ... the relationship of emotions to intelligence. First, sensations of pain and pleasure drive thought, in the sense that they establish values for thinking and striving to achieve or avoid some event or condition. Sensation triggers emotions and in turn triggers sensations which may act as second-level motivators. They also may trigger subsystems for readiness (or inhibition) of action. (Example: hunger depletes blood sugar, triggering anger when a certain level of stress is reached, which releases adrenalin which energizes the body. Anger also may cause partly or fully random action, which is statistically better than apathy for killing or harvesting something to eat.) At least that's the more traditional outlook on emotions--though that outlook may have changed in ten years or so since I did much reading in psychology. Even if true, however, the above outlook doesn't establish a necessary link of emotion with artificial thought; humans can supply the goals and values for a Mars Rover, an activate command can trigger emergency energy reserves. Some other more intimate association of emotion with thought is needed. Perhaps emotions affect thought in beneficial ways, say improving the thinking mechanism itself. (The notion that it impedes correct thought is too conventional and (worse) obvious to be interesting.) Or maybe emotion IS thought in some way. It is, after all, only a conclusion based on incomplete brain evidence that thought is electrical in nature. Suppose the electrical action of the brain is secondary, that the biochemical action of the brain is the primary mechanism of thought. This might square with the observation that decision often happens in the subconscious, very rapidly, and integrates several (or even dozens) of conflicting motives into a vector sum. In other words, an analog computer may be a better model for human thought than a digital one. (In the nature of things that answer is likely too simple. Most likely, I'd guess, the brain is a hybrid of the two.) Larry @ jpl-vlsi