[net.politics.theory] Nozick on Imposing Risk

kort@hounx.UUCP (B.KORT) (02/04/86)

Paul Torek reviews Nozick on the "boundary crossing" issue.  The
question arises, should one negotiate advance permission (and
compensation, if appropriate) before crossing another person's
boundary, or is it sufficient to compensate afterwards.

The dilemma arises because an agent does not have sufficient
advance knowledge of where the other person draws the line,
especially for first-time activities.  Imagine saying to a
midwestern farmer in 1952, "Hello, I'm from the Bell Sytem
and were putting in a microwave relay system.  Do you mind if
we shoot a 10 Watt beam of 4 GHz microwaves across your farm?"

Conversely, the mere act of expressing a preference may cross
the boundary of the person on the receiving end of the sentiment.
There is a current lyric in the popular music scene, "You have
no right to tell me how you feel."  If the utterer of this sentiment
holds it true for himself, then by symmetry he may be violating
the very same boundary when he expresses the sentiment to someone
else.

The bottom line is that permissions grow with maturity, and the
crossing of boundaries is unavoidable without perfect knowledge.
Perfect knowledge requires essentially infinite information
interchange rates, which far exceed the capacity of the human
I/O channels

--Barry Kort 

janw@inmet.UUCP (02/07/86)

[--Paul V. Torek      torek@umich]
The invitation was either to defend Nozick or improve on him.
I'll try to do the latter.

>" ... one might place [rights] as side constraints upon the actions to be 
>done:  don't violate constraints C.  The rights of others determine the
>constraints upon your actions." (29)

Except where rights significantly overlap, as is sometimes inevitable,
as illustrated by some pollution examples.

>"Political philosophy is concerned only with *certain* ways that persons
>may not use others; primarily, physically aggressing against them. ...
>Side constraints express the inviolability of others, in the ways they
>specify." (32)

"May not" together with "political philosophy" introduces an ele-
ment  of  ambiguity:  *morally* or *legally* may not ? Should the
immoral be always illegal? I say, definitely not. Should  society
and  its  laws  be so arranged that they make physical aggression
*impossible* ?  Definitely not. It is unethical; ways of prevent-
ing it may be even more unethical.

>"A line (or hyper-plane) circumscribes an area in moral space around an
>individual.

Only in some ideal space. In life, the areas overlap.  Does  that
mean  that  demarcating them is a bad idea?  Not at all, but such
demarcation is necessarily approximate, and grey areas are  inev-
itable.

>... the following question arises:  *Are others forbidden to
>perform actions that transgress the boundary or encroach upon the 
>circumscribed area, or are they permitted to perform such actions
>provided that they compensate the person whose boundary has been crossed*?

Ethically forbidden or legally forbidden ? If the area is, with
reasonable approximation, a "white" area of one person's right,
then *ethically* encroachment is forbidden, period.
If it is a "grey" area of overlapping rights, then side constraints
don't apply, and the ethical problem is that of maximizing a fairness
functional. Usually the best solution is some constructive compromise,
something creative and completely unexpected.

Now, *legal* problems. Insofar as the law is simply for the  gui-
dance of the two parties, it approximates, imperfectly, the ethi-
cal principle. The imperfection in the "grey" case is obvious  as
the creative solution can't be codified (but a list of precedents
may be helpful). In the "white" case a simple  "shalt  not"  suf-
fices;  but  the difficulty and the necessary imperfection lie in
classifying the case as "white", since no two situations are  the
same.

So far, non-coercive law. *Enforceable* law  introduces  a  third
party  (the  state, the neighbors, the godfather) which is ready,
to an extent, to side with the "right" side. This opens a  danger
of  rights  violation  far worse than those under dispute.  In no
case is such a law an  even  approximate  embodiment  of  ethical
principle.  

At most, it can be  *useful*  :  utilitarian  considerations  may
morally  justify it as long as ethical principle is not violated.
E.g., boycott, consisting of actions that  are  in  themselves
within  the  actors'  right, violates fewer ethical constraints
than imprisonment. Even so, any *punishment* violates an  ethical
constraint,  being  a  *malicious*  act,  *intentionally* causing
suffering. *Prevention* of crime - e.g., knocking out a  bully  -
is morally far superior to punishment.

It may turn out that some ethical rules *have* to be violated, to
avoid  violating  even  more  basic rules. This admission deletes
them from the list of side constraints, turning  them  into  mere
desiderata.  But if some kind of evil is necessary, it is no rea-
son to tolerate *another* kind of evil.

The following *ethical equality* axiom is proposed: if an act  is
forbidden,  as  a  matter  of principle, to one individual, it is
forbidden to any other. E.g., if I may not impose a tax  on  you,
neither  should the Congress. But if you are allowed to protect
me from a mugger by force, so is the policeman.

This sets a limit on the activity of those who enforce  the  law,
and of necessity leaves some ethical principles *unenforced*.  It
leaves the world imperfect. So be it.

>... Let us say that a system forbids an action to a person if it imposes
>(is geared to impose) some penalty upon him for doing the act, in addition
>to exacting compensation from him for the act's victims." (57)

Such a system is morally obnoxious. All  punishment  is  abomina-
tion.   It  may  be a necessary evil (though I doubt it), but the
question belongs with that of the necessity of Hiroshima.

>----------------------------------
>Alert readers will note that Nozick has changed the subject.  His question
>is an ETHICAL question, but he immediately proceeds to talk about POLITICAL
>systems, and never returns to the explicitly ethical question within the
>chapter.  We, however, will keep the question "what is an *individual* to
>do?" firmly in mind.
>----------------------------------

Very true. He's changed the subject, and, as stated above, did it
in  a  morally  offensive  way. I'll insist on separating the two
even more sharply than you do.

>" ... Our discussion of the first question we posed near the beginning
>of this chapter -- `Why not permit all boundary crossings provided 
>compensation is paid?' -- has led us to the second question posed there --
>`Why not prohibit all boundary crossings to which the victim has not
>consented in advance?'

Permitted *by whom* ? Prohibited *by whom* ? By one's conscience ?
Or by "Society" ?

>-----------------------------------
>Nozick has given NO reason for departing ONE WHIT from the recommendation
>of his `second question' -- at least not when we consider the ethical
>question.  Accidents, perhaps, should not be punished by the political
>system; but aside from them the same goes for political theory.  THIS IS
>THE NOZICK WHO TELLS US THAT INDIVIDUALS ARE INVIOLATE!  So to repeat his
>question (slightly rephrased to be explicitly ethical):  Why *aren't* I
>prohibited from all boundary crossings to which my victim has not
>consented in advance? 
>-----------------------------------

You *are* - morally - unless there is a conflict of rights -  and
using reasonable approximation. You are not constrained to *more*
than that, because this is *impossible*.  And,  as  you  yourself
say, no reason has been given to demand less than that.

This does not mean *at all* that "Society" has a right, by  what-
ever  means  it  takes,  to exact from you the full value of your
moral obligation. The goal - restoring violated right  -  may  or
may not justify the means. Usually it does not.

Conclusion: Nozick is not my kind of libertarian. He is a collec-
tivist,  a  state fetishist and a social engineer:
--Behind all his "Should X be forbidden or permitted"  stand  the
"We", the consensus, forbidding or permitting (collectivism),
--delegating that function to a State with a  monopoly  of  coer-
cion, above moral rules that individuals obey (state fetishism);
--and a perfect social system is constructed from  first  princi-
ples  by a master engineer, to constrain the rest of us to virtu-
ous behavior.
The state, the consensus and the author are presiding in a  court
where  the individual sits squarely in the dock. 

By sheer chance, the perfect system has less government than  the
current  one. Lucky us. But, as you correctly state, even that is
achieved through an inconsistency.

		Jan Wasilewsky

torek@umich.UUCP (Paul V. Torek ) (02/13/86)

>> = Nozick (quoted by Torek), > = janw@inmet.  The first part of this
article is my response to Jan W.; the rest answers questions on Nozick which
probably won't interest many readers.

>>" ... one might place [rights] as side constraints upon the actions to be 
>>done:  don't violate constraints C.  The rights of others determine the
>>constraints upon your actions." (29)
>
>Except where rights significantly overlap, as is sometimes inevitable,
>as illustrated by some pollution examples.

>>"A line (or hyper-plane) circumscribes an area in moral space around an
>>individual.
>
>Only in some ideal space. In life, the areas overlap.  Does  that
>mean  that  demarcating them is a bad idea?  Not at all, but such
>demarcation is necessarily approximate, and grey areas are  inev-
>itable.

>>... the following question arises:  *Are others forbidden to
>>perform actions that transgress the boundary or encroach upon the 
>>circumscribed area, or are they permitted to perform such actions
>>provided that they compensate the person whose boundary has been crossed*?
>
>Ethically forbidden or legally forbidden ? If the area is, with
>reasonable approximation, a "white" area of one person's right,
>then *ethically* encroachment is forbidden, period.
>If it is a "grey" area of overlapping rights, then side constraints
>don't apply, and the ethical problem is that of maximizing a fairness
>functional. Usually the best solution is some constructive compromise,
>something creative and completely unexpected.

Although you have certainly distinguished your position from Nozick's,
this leaves a lot of questions unanswered.  How do you identify which
areas are "grey"?  How should one deal with conflicting grey-area-rights,
i.e. what is the "fairness function" that should be maximized?  I'm not
asking for a justification of the principles you would use here (though
they shouldn't be ad hoc), just a description of those principles.  One
that doesn't circularly use moral terms (e.g., "you should do what's 
right" obviously wouldn't cut it).

>It may turn out that some ethical rules *have* to be violated, to
>avoid  violating  even  more  basic rules. This admission deletes
>them from the list of side constraints, turning  them  into  mere
>desiderata.  But if some kind of evil is necessary, it is no rea-
>son to tolerate *another* kind of evil.

Again, certain obvious questions arise.  What makes a rule more basic?

>The following *ethical equality* axiom is proposed: if an act  is
>forbidden,  as  a  matter  of principle, to one individual, it is
>forbidden to any other. E.g., if I may not impose a tax  on  you,
>neither  should the Congress. But if you are allowed to protect
>me from a mugger by force, so is the policeman.

This sounds tempting even to a nonlibertarian like me, but I think you're
ignoring the fact that institutional rules and roles can make a difference
in what act is being performed.  Whether an act counts as "act X" or "act
Y", or even whether it counts as an intelligible act at all, depends on a 
social context.  (See Alisdair MacIntyre's _After Virtue_ for an overdose
of this point.)  Of course, there may be *some* descriptions of acts
which are social-context-neutral, but I see NO REASON to suppose without
argument that these are the only descriptions which can legitimately figure
in a moral theory.

---End intersting debate.  Begin boring exegesis of Nozick.  Hit 'n' now!---

>>"Political philosophy is concerned only with *certain* ways that persons
>>may not use others; primarily, physically aggressing against them. ...
>>Side constraints express the inviolability of others, in the ways they
>>specify." (32)
>
>"May not" together with "political philosophy" introduces an ele-
>ment  of  ambiguity:  *morally* or *legally* may not ?

Since the chapter I lifted this from was devoted to moral theory, I think
he means "morally may not".

>>" ... Our discussion of the first question we posed near the beginning
>>of this chapter -- `Why not permit all boundary crossings provided 
>>compensation is paid?' -- has led us to the second question posed there --
>>`Why not prohibit all boundary crossings to which the victim has not
>>consented in advance?'
>
>Permitted *by whom* ? Prohibited *by whom* ? By one's conscience ?
>Or by "Society" ?

The context of the chapter suggests Nozick meant "society" there.

>Conclusion: Nozick is not my kind of libertarian. He is a collec-
>tivist,  a  state fetishist and a social engineer:
>--Behind all his "Should X be forbidden or permitted"  stand  the
>"We", the consensus, forbidding or permitting (collectivism),
>--delegating that function to a State with a  monopoly  of  coer-
>cion, above moral rules that individuals obey (state fetishism);

These charges against Nozick, given your point of view, seem basically
fair to me.

>--and a perfect social system is constructed from  first  princi-
>ples  by a master engineer, to constrain the rest of us to virtu-
>ous behavior.

This one doesn't.  I don't think Nozick has claimed to find the perfect,
or even the best, social system.  He fudges over a lot of questions and
admits it.

--Paul Torek						torek@umich