[net.politics.theory] Liberalism, Part IV

carnes@gargoyle.UUCP (Richard Carnes) (03/09/86)

Continuing with the excerpts from "Liberalism" by Ronald Dworkin:
______________

I said that the conservative holds one among a number of possible
alternatives to the liberal conception of equality.  Each of these
alternatives shares the opinion that treating a person with respect
requires treating him as the good man would wish to be treated.  The
conservative supposes that the good man would wish to be treated in
accordance with the principles of a special sort of society, which I
shall call the virtuous society....

Suppose a conservative is asked to draft a constitution for a society
generally like ours, which he believes to be virtuous.  Like the
liberal, he will see great merit in the familiar institutions of
political democracy and an economic market.  The appeal of these
institutions will be very different for the conservative, however.
The economic market, in practice, assigns greater rewards to those
who, because they have the virtues of talent and industry, supply
more of what is wanted by the other members of the virtuous society;
and that is, for the conservative, the paradigm of fairness in
distribution.  Political democracy distributes opportunities, through
the provisions of civil and criminal law, as the citizens of a
virtuous society wish [them] to be distributed....

The liberal, as I said, finds the market defective principally
because it allows morally irrelevant differences to affect
distribution.... But the conservative prizes just the feature of the
market that puts a premium on talents prized by the community,
because these are, in a virtuous community, virtues.  So he will find
no genuine merit, but only expediency, in the idea of redistribution.
He will allow room, of course, for the virtue of charity, for it is a
virtue that is part of the public catalogue; but he will prefer
private charity to public, because it is a purer expression of that
virtue....

The economic market distributes rewards for talents valued in the
virtuous society, but since these talents are unequally distributed,
wealth will be concentrated, and the wealthy will be at the mercy of
an envious political majority anxious to take by law what it cannot
take by talent.... [Instead of restricting the franchise] the
conservative will find more appeal in the different, and politically
much more feasible, idea of rights to property.

These rights have the same force, though of course radically
different content, as the liberal's civil rights.  The liberal will,
for his own purposes, accept some right to property, because he will
count some sovereignty over a range of personal possessions essential
to dignity.  But the conservative will strive for rights to property
of a very different order; he will want rights that protect, not some
minimum dominion over a range of possessions independently shown to
be desirable, but an unlimited dominion over whatever has been
acquired through an institution that defines and rewards talent....

The distinction between equality of opportunity and equality of
result is crucial to the conservative:  the institutions of the
economic market and representative democracy cannot achieve what he
supposes they do unless each citizen has an equal opportunity to
capitalize on his genuine talents and other virtues in the contest
these institutions provide.  But since the conservative knows that
these virtues are unequally distributed, he also knows that equality
of opportunity must have been denied if the outcome of the contest is
equality of result....

[The conservative] will steadily oppose any form of `affirmative
action' that offers special opportunities, like places in medical
school or jobs, on criteria other than some proper conception of the
virtue appropriate to the reward....

Liberalism cannot be based on scepticism.  Its constitutive morality
provides that human beings must be treated as equals by their
government, not because there is no right and wrong in political
morality, but because that is what is right.  Liberalism does not
rest on any special theory of personality, nor does it deny that most
human beings will think that what is good for them is that they be
active in society.  Liberalism is not self-contradictory:  the
liberal conception of equality is a principle of political
organization that is required by justice, not a way of life for
individuals....

[But another objection, that liberalism denies to political society
its highest function and ultimate justification, which is that
society must help its members to achieve what is in fact good] cannot
so easily be set aside.  There is no easy way to demonstrate the
proper role in institutions that have a monopoly of power over the
lives of others; reasonable and moral men will disagree.  The issue
is at bottom the issue I identified:  what is the content of the
respect that is necessary to dignity and independence?

That raises problems in moral philosophy and in the philosophy of
mind that are fundamental for political theory though not discussed
here; but this essay does bear on one issue sometime thought to be
relevant.  It is sometimes said that liberalism must be wrong because
it assumes that the opinions people have about the sort of lives they
want are self-generated, whereas these opinions are in fact that
products of the economic system or other aspects of the society in
which they live.... Liberalism responds to the claim, that
preferences are caused by systems of distribution, with the sensible
answer that in that case it is all the more important that
distribution be fair in itself, not as tested by the preferences it
produces.  --Ronald Dworkin
-- 
Richard Carnes, ihnp4!gargoyle!carnes

laura@hoptoad.uucp (Laura Creighton) (03/11/86)

In article <364@gargoyle.UUCP> carnes@gargoyle.UUCP (Richard Carnes) writes:
>Continuing with the excerpts from "Liberalism" by Ronald Dworkin:
>______________

By and large I think that Dworkin describes what is today called
``conservatism'' well.  But is is worth noting that what he is
describing used to be called liberalism, and indeed is part of what
Milton Freidman still calls liberalism.

>I said that the conservative holds one among a number of possible
>alternatives to the liberal conception of equality.  Each of these
>alternatives shares the opinion that treating a person with respect
>requires treating him as the good man would wish to be treated.  The
>conservative supposes that the good man would wish to be treated in
>accordance with the principles of a special sort of society, which I
>shall call the virtuous society....

Here I think that Dworkin misses it; the statment is right but the
perspective is wrong.  The conservative does not believe that virtue
is defined by the virtuous society, but rather that virtuous men
create a virtuous society through the expression of their own virtue.
The purpose of society, thus, to the extent that a conservative can
say that society has a purpose is to *promote virtue*.  And one of the
many ways it promotes virtue is by rewarding it.

>Suppose a conservative is asked to draft a constitution for a society
>generally like ours, which he believes to be virtuous.

Phrased that way, the conservative will give up in disgust.  However,
a conservative can be asked to draft a consitution for a society which
is virtuous (or promotes virtue) and will come up with a society
generally like ours.

>[But another objection, that liberalism denies to political society
>its highest function and ultimate justification, which is that
>society must help its members to achieve what is in fact good] cannot
>so easily be set aside.  There is no easy way to demonstrate the
>proper role in institutions that have a monopoly of power over the
>lives of others; reasonable and moral men will disagree.  The issue
>is at bottom the issue I identified:  what is the content of the
>respect that is necessary to dignity and independence?

If Dworkin is truly interested in dignity and independence, doesn't he
see a strong conflict between monopoly of power and independence?
Why does this not lead him to conclude that few if any institutions should
have a monopoly of power, simply because that decreases independence?

I think that a fundamental distiction which Dworkin misses out on in this
essay is the objective or subjective nature of ``the good''.  Dworkin
keeps on plugging for ``a conservative believes that a virtuous society
determines the good'' (which is moral subjectivism) whereas all the
conservatives I know are moral objectivists.  This trait is shared
even though there is strong disagreement between conservatives as to
what is the basis of this moral standard -- God, human nature, evolutionary
pressure, or a simple ``but that is the way it is''.

-- 
Laura Creighton		
ihnp4!hoptoad!laura  utzoo!hoptoad!laura  sun!hoptoad!laura
toad@lll-crg.arpa

franka@mmintl.UUCP (Frank Adams) (03/15/86)

In article <607@hoptoad.uucp> laura@hoptoad.UUCP (Laura Creighton) writes:
>In article <364@gargoyle.UUCP> carnes@gargoyle.UUCP (Richard Carnes) writes:
>>Continuing with the excerpts from "Liberalism" by Ronald Dworkin:
>
>By and large I think that Dworkin describes what is today called
>``conservatism'' well.  But is is worth noting that what he is
>describing used to be called liberalism, and indeed is part of what
>Milton Freidman still calls liberalism.

I think it is more accurate to say that traditional liberalism has become
the standard in Western democracies, and that mainstream liberalism and
mainstream conservatism are both derived from it.

Frank Adams                           ihnp4!philabs!pwa-b!mmintl!franka
Multimate International    52 Oakland Ave North    E. Hartford, CT 06108

janw@inmet.UUCP (03/17/86)

[    Adam Reed (ihnp4!npois!adam)]
>Of the other two names on the list - Hobbes and Spinoza - neither
>qualifies as a Liberal.

Right about Hobbes. I must really object on  behalf  of  Spinoza,
not to nitpick, but because he is one of my favorites.

>Spinoza held that individual will, and thus  individual  freedom,
>was an illusion.

A very simplistic view of Spinoza's determinism. Suffice it here
to say that his whole teaching was on how to *achieve* individual
freedom. 

>His pantheistic metaphysics led to an ethics based on the premise
>that  "Whatever  exists  is God". The political corrolary of this
>view is acquiescence in whatever exists.

It certainly was not for him. He discussed at length which
forms of government are preferable to others.

>The Panglossian secularization of the above ("All is for the best in
>the best of all possible worlds") was the intellectual foundation of
>early conservatism, and was mercilessly ridiculed, from an
>uncompromising classical Liberal perspective, by Voltaire.

Pangloss was, of course, a caricature of  Leibnitz's  philosophy,
not Spinoza's. (To whom the quote above belongs).  Voltaire had a
high opinion of Spinoza (without really understanding him).

>While Spinoza's refusal of a royal pension from Louis  XIV  tells
>us  a  great deal about his personal integrity, the fact that the
>pension was offered tells us even more about the  political  uses
>and implications of his philosophy.

No such uses were, of course, made.

Louis's interests in Holland had nothing to do  with  philosophy.
He  made, however, a show of encouraging culture. The pension was
on condition of Spinoza dedicating a book to the  king.   It  may
have also had to do with party politics in Holland, in which Spi-
noza was, for a while, involved. In that case - the pension offer
was an attempt to neutralize an *opponent*.

There is absolutely no doubt that had someone explained to Louis
XIV the contents of *any* of Spinoza's books, the ultra-catholic
Sun King would forthwith become his enemy.

In philosophy, Spinoza was a proponent of free inquiry, of  indi-
vidualism,  of  rational  self-interest,  and  of  reason  as the
supreme vurtue.

In political theory, he was an advocate of democracy based
on freedom of opinion.

In practical politics, he was a friend and supporter of De Witt,
the leader of the liberal, republican party.

(None of the above purports to explain Spinoza's philosophy,
just to defend his liberal reputation).

		Jan Wasilewsky

janw@inmet.UUCP (03/17/86)

Correcting a misleading phrase:

>>The Panglossian secularization of the above ("All is for the best in
>>the best of all possible worlds") was the intellectual foundation of
>>early conservatism, and was mercilessly ridiculed, from an
>>uncompromising classical Liberal perspective, by Voltaire.

[me]
>Pangloss was, of course, a caricature of  Leibnitz's  philosophy,
>not Spinoza's. (To whom the quote above belongs).  Voltaire had a
>high opinion of Spinoza (without really understanding him).

I meant that the quote is of Leibnitz, not Spinoza.  Spinoza  be-
lieved all exists that is possible, not just the "best".