[net.books] Time and Immortality

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (09/26/83)

AN AFTERLIFE? CHILDISH FAIRY TALES!  After all, consciousness depends 
only upon the brain.  But wait...Science has shown that the flow of
time is a subjective reality--that the past "still" exists.
"Time Twins, a nonsupernatural concept of survival after death," by
Henry Friedman, explains how time itself ensures our survival--in the
future as well as the past.

Reply by mail if you are interested in the above manuscript for the
revised and enlarged second edition of the above book.    If
enough interest is shown, portions of it can be electronically published
on this net (in short  installments).  A table of contents and capsule
outline is included below.  The concept includes some parapsychology,
e.g., telepathy and synchronicity, which some might find of dubious
worth, but large portions of the book are fairly soundly based in modern
physics.
 
    Introduction
 
 1. Is Yesterday Really Gone?

Two opposing philosophies of time.  The meaning of time as the fourth
dimension.  Free will, determinism, and the "many worlds" concept of
quantum physics.

 2. What a Coincidence--

Jung's concept of meaningful coincidences (synchronicity). Explanations
of meaningful coincidences from modern physics.  Archetypal dreams
and images.  The relationship of synchronicity to such paranormal
phenomena as the "I Ching" and astrology.  The cyclical view of time.

 3. --There You are Again!

"Reincarnation experiences" explained as mental communication through
time between different persons with like personalities: the concept of
time twins.  The predictability of time twins by synchronicity.

 4. Whispers in Time

Additional support for precognition, telepathy, etc., from quantum
physics and astrophysics.  Unconscious mental communication among time
twins.    Can time twins be considered a type of survival after death?
A paradox: different persons, yet the same person.

 5. So What's New?

New models of reality relegate former "truths" to the role of figurative
constructs.  If this process, so natural in the physical sciences, is
thwarted in the domain of religion by blind literalism, we are
eventually deprived of our faith.  Multiple realities and the mythic
dimension.
 
 6. "Who Knows Where or When?"

Do the ideas treated in this book offer any hope for a reunion with
our loved ones after death?  The psychology of coping with change.
The idea of belonging to a particular period of time.

 7. Gathering Data

Some suggestions for experiments to test the hypotheses presented in
this book.  An explanation of the "twins clock paradox" of special
relativity and its relationship to the possibility of time travel.

 8. A New Heritage

A summary of the ideas presented to this point.  New significance for
the role of the individual.  Two opposing models of the "end of time."
A new type of data bank.

 9. Ghosts, Mediums, and the Astral Plane

Suppositions concerning other areas of the paranormal, based upon
the ideas about time discussed earlier.  Interpenetrating universes
and multiple pasts.

10. The Arrow of Time

Does time really flow?    A clear explanation for the layman of a
complex subject (motion picture analogies are used for ease of under-
standing).  How humankind participates in the very process of creation.
Zeno and Parmenides: the two sages from Elea.  Some cosmological
implications of time.

11. Another Type of Picture, Another Type of Wave

Paranormal ramifications of the holographic process of photography
and Pribram's holographic model of human memory.  The concept of
"synchronicity waves."    Is there a super-reality, from which all other
realities are, as it were, projected?

12. In Your Spirit's Spirit

The mechanism of our survival in the perpetual past via infinite waves
of consciousness rippling across time.    Is there a transfer of aware-
ness into the past at death?  Parallels are then drawn between Jung's
description of the many different meanings of the word "spirit" and
the concepts of immortality discussed in this book.  The power of the
mythic dimension of life.

13. A Scene from the Future

Some implications for religion and philosophy of rapid advances in
artificial intelligence.

14. Reflections from Warped Time

The humorous side of a profound subject.

15. Time: God's Monument to Man

Concluding meditation, tinged with personal nostalgia for my lost
childhood and college years.  Time and the search for a purposeful
universe.

--- Henry Friedman (the author)
 

dya@unc-c.UUCP (09/27/83)

References: hlexa.202


Full-Name: David Anthony
Organisation: The University of North Carolina at Charlotte

      Yes! One vote for "a chapter a week" posted to the net, if possible
Traffic on net.books has become very slow lately.


                      {.....duke!mcnc!unc-c!urp!dya }

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (10/13/83)

		(c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
		    (Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		  Is Yesterday Really Gone? (continued)

       There is	an analogy that	is often used to describe our  ina-
       bility,	as three-dimensional creatures,	to fully comprehend
       a four-dimensional universe. We are  asked  to  imagine	the
       plight  of hypothetical two-dimensional creatures living	in,
       as they see it, a flat, two-dimensional	world.	 Physicists
       and  mathematicians belonging to	this flat world	might some-
       day discover that there was a wider, three-dimensional real-
       ity.   They  might  even	 describe such a universe of three-
       dimensional cubes and  spheres,	etc.,  mathematically,	but
       they  would  be	unable	to  fully  visualize  such  strange
       objects.

       The closest the	two-dimensional	 creatures  could  come	 to
       visualizing a cube would	be as a	series of separate squares;
       they might see a	sphere as  a  series  of  circles.   Analo-
       gously, we, as three-dimensional	creatures, can only visual-
       ize four-dimensional  spacetime	as  a  series  of  separate
       events.

       One element of a	four-dimensional universe that	might  dis-
       turb  many  is  its  apparent determinism.  If future events
       already exist, what would be the	meaning	of saying  that	 we
       have free will?

       There are several different ways	to address such	 questions.
       Some  philosophers  say	that  the  question  of	determinism
       versus free will	is not decided one way or the other by	the
       idea  of	 a  four-dimensional  universe.	  For "determinism"
       means not only that a future event is  fixed,  or  definite,
       but  also  that	it  could  be  definitely predicted *in	the
       present*	if enough of the causal	 details  were	known.	 In
       other   words,	determinism  is	 the  traditional  idea	 in
       Newtonian physics of a  "clockwork  universe,"  whose  every
       condition  is  inexorably  dictated  by	its "initial condi-
       tions."	In such	a clockwork universe causality would  reign
       supreme.

       However,	the concept of a deterministic,	clockwork world	has
       been  largely  discredited  by  quantum mechanics, which	has
       shown that the behavior of  subatomic  particles	 is  essen-
       tially random.  The further implication is that such random-
       ness may	also apply to much of the larger world of  everyday
       reality.	 So  one  could	 argue that the	proper term for	the
       state of	future events in a world of four-dimensional space-
       time  is	"determinateness" (definiteness), not "determinism"
       (clockwork causality).

       Others would add	that questions about free will	are  essen-
       tially  meaningless, anyway.  For whether or not	we actually
       have free will, we have no choice but to	act as if we do.

       All of the above	arguments notwithstanding, some	of us might
       be  deeply  disturbed  by the idea that our futures are com-
       pletely	decided.   And	there  is  still  another  possible
       interpretation  of the future in	a four-dimensional universe
       that is neither determinate  nor	 deterministic.	  Physicist
       Paul Davies  ("Other  Worlds") and science writer Gary Zukav
       ("The Dancing Wu	Li Masters") describe a	 new  concept  that
       has arisen as one possible explanation for some of the para-
       doxes inherent in  quantum  theory:  the	 concept  of  "many
       worlds,"	 also  called  "parallel universes" or "alternative
       possibilities."

       In quantum mechanics, the random	paths and behavior of suba-
       tomic particles are described by	mathematical equations that
       give the	probabilities for the possible ways a particle	can
       act  (Schroedinger  wave	 equations).   In  the conventional
       interpretation of these equations, the actual observation of
       a particular path for a particle	causes the alternative pos-
       sible paths to "collapse" into non-existence.  In  contrast,
       the concept of parallel universes states	that every possible
       path continues to exist	--  in a  separate  branch  of	the
       universe!

		(This chapter to be concluded in Part 3.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (Henry Friedman) (10/17/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		  Is Yesterday Really Gone? (conclusion)

       In  his	book   "Timewarps,"   astrophysicist   John Gribbin
       explains	 that  he  prefers  this  new  concept	of parallel
       universes because it restores the meaning of free will.	The
       concept,	 in  effect,  adds  a  fifth  dimension	to the four
       dimensions of spacetime,	i.e., the  dimension  of  alternate
       possibilities.	In  the	photographic analogy, we could com-
       pare the	four-dimensional concept of the	universe to a  sin-
       gle  long  reel	of film.  In contrast, the five-dimensional
       universe	of alternate possibilities  would  be  compared	 to
       many  reels  of film.  At each point of choice of action	(or
       possibility of diverse random paths), the film would  branch
       into  new films,	one for	each possible outcome, just as film
       makers sometimes	now shoot for different	possible endings.

       For example, in one universe, at	a  given  place	 and  time,
       there  might  be	 an  unspoiled	meadowland.   In a parallel
       universe	at the corresponding place, there might	be  a  busy
       airport,	 a  result of different	decisions by government	and
       developers.  Key	portions of the	concepts to be developed in
       this  book hinge	largely	upon parallel universes.  So I will
       again stress the	point that, although the idea has not  been
       proved,	it is a	serious	hypothesis arising from	advances in
       quantum physics	--  not	merely an invention of science fan-
       tasy writers.

       In the novel "Slaughterhouse-Five," by  Kurt  Vonnegut, Jr.,
       based  upon  the	 World	War II fire-bombing of Dresden,	the
       hero bounces randomly backward and  forward  in	time  among
       different  events of his	life, including	his death.  At each
       point of	his re-emergence, he fully "remembers"	the  entire
       fabric  of his life, past and future.  Although he knows	how
       and when	he will	die, he	also believes in  his  immortality,
       since no	moment of his life ever	ceases to exist.

       Now, you	might object that such ideas are fine  for  novels,
       but  that  nothing  in science, including relativity, states
       that we can travel into the past.  In relativity	jargon,	the
       path  of	 an  object  through spacetime is called its "world
       line," and in spacetime	diagrams,  the	world  line  of	 an
       object always travels forward in	time.  So what is the mean-
       ing, one	might ask, of saying the past still  exists  if	 it
       cannot  be  reached.   Such questions will be discussed more
       fully in	later chapters,	as the full concept  is	 developed.
       But for now, I'd	like you to try	another	mental experiment.

       Look at a photograph of a deceased friend or relative, not a
       studio  portrait,  but one showing him or her in	a familiar,
       natural setting.	 As you	gaze at	the picture, the person	may
       seem  so	 alive	and  vital that	you have to remind yourself
       that he is dead,	and that the happy time	 when  the  picture
       was  taken is gone forever.  But	instead	of concentrating on
       that cold reality, pretend, for a moment, that the scene	and
       time  of	 the  photograph still exists  --  "some-when"	--
       and that	the person is really still just	as  alive  in  that
       time  as	he seems in the	picture.  Perhaps you'll find, even
       if only for a moment, that the idea rings true.

       Of course, mental experiments like the one above	prove noth-
       ing  (though they may convey the	flavor of some of the ideas
       in this book). And even if such a concept of spacetime  were
       true,  we  could	 not  form a very satisfying hypothesis	for
       immortality on that basis alone:	 one  lifetime,	 frozen	 in
       time,  with  no	possibility  for further development, would
       hardly constitute immortality, as we usually  think  of	the
       meaning of the word.

       No,  there  are	other  components  to  be  introduced	and
       developed  before  the concept is complete.  And	it is hoped
       that the	whole will prove to be more than just  the  sum	 of
       its parts.

			      End of Chapter

       (This series of excerpts	to be continued	in Part	4. Comments
       and  criticisms	by mail	are welcome at any time.  I may	not
       be able to reply	to each	comment	individually, but all  com-
       ments  will be carefully	considered.  When there	is silence,
       I begin to wonder  whether  anyone  is  still  reading  this
       series of articles!)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (10/25/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

			    The	Arrow of Time

       As stated in Part 2, we are, as it  were,  three-dimensional
       creatures  living  in  a	four-dimensional world.	 We see	the
       world changing, things moving,  time  flowing  from  present
       into future.  Yet the new reality of spacetime suggests that
       such  appearances  are  an  illusion,  that  everything	 is
       "already	there,"	statically arrayed in spacetime.

       Let's return to the motion picture analogy to  help  clarify
       these  two  opposing views of reality.  Imagine that we have
       unrolled	the reels of film from a long movie onto the  floor
       of  a  gymnasium,  laying  the  film  in	a spiral around	the
       floor.  Then, imagine that we have  climbed  onto  a  raised
       platform	in the center of the gym, with a very powerful pair
       of binoculars, from where we  can  see  all  of	the  frames
       spread out before us.  The movie	frames can be compared to a
       portion of our universe,	spread out in time.

       Since we	can choose any single frame of our movie  and  call
       it  "now,"  past	 and future on the film	are merely relative
       directions, not specific	sections of film.   All	 frames	 in
       one  direction from the frame we	selected as "now" represent
       the past, and all the frames in the opposite direction along
       the  strip  represent  the future.  If we became	disoriented
       and forgot which	direction was  which  along  the  spiraling
       strip,  we could	easily verify it.  We could use	our binocu-
       lars to search for any type of event in the movie that would
       be  nonreversible  in everyday life.  For example, if we	saw
       in one frame that a character in	the movie was in a swimming
       pool  and,  as  we  followed along the strip, he	or she rose
       from the	water and eventually landed on a diving	 board,	 we
       would  know  that  we  had  been	moving along the strip in a
       direction toward	the past.

       If we picked a frame, examined it and then looked at another
       frame,  far enough from the first, we would notice that peo-
       ple or things had *moved* or *changed*.	However, if we then
       cut  out	 several of such frames	in which change	was notice-
       able, placed them in front of us	and looked at them  all	 at
       once,  nothing  would  really seem to be	*moving* or *chang-
       ing*, in	the everyday sense of time: everything	would  just
       be "already there," all at once.	 But if	we were	then to	run
       a strip of the film through a movie projector and  view	it,
       the everyday sense of time would	immediately return.  People
       and things in our movie would again seem	to  be	moving	and
       changing	and becoming in	time.  And time	would *flow* again,
       as the point of time called the present	continually  became
       the past, and the future	revealed itself	as the present.

       And  that  is  our  everyday  view  of  time:  not  a  four-
       dimensional continuum, but merely a measure of the continual
       processes of change (relative to	processes that appear *uni-
       form*,  such  as	 the  rotation	of the earth on	its axis or
       around the sun, or the vibrations of atoms  in  a  crystal).
       Gary  Zukav  ("The Dancing Wu Li	Masters") compares our lim-
       ited, everyday view of time to viewing spacetime	 through  a
       narrow slit in a	piece of cardboard.  It	is if the cardboard
       were moving to reveal only the single moment  of	 time  that
       lay  behind the slit.  This is like our motion picture pass-
       ing in front of the projector aperture, one frame at a time.

       But why is this so?  Why	*are* we limited to seeing time	 as
       a  flow	of  changes?   Musn't the "arrow of time" be, after
       all, embedded in	the fundamental	reality	 of  our  universe?
       The  philosopher	of the "manifold" would	agree that there is
       an arrow, as far	as the aspect of *direction* is	 concerned,
       but  not	 that  the arrow *moves*.  We know that	time is	not
       the same	in all directions,  as	evidenced  by  the  law	 of
       entropy	(the  diffusion	 of energy always increases) and by
       nonreversible causal processes.	The probability	is very	low
       that  a	dynamited  building will reconstruct itself or that
       all the molecules of perfume will ever return to	the bottle.
       But  the	 fact that time	has direction does not require that
       it *flow*.

       In everyday reality, however,  things  move  and	 change	 in
       time.   So  doesn't  there have to be something unique about
       that ever-moving	point of time that we call "now," the  only
       point of	time that we ever seem to experience?

       Adolf Gruenbaum addresses the above questions  in  his  book
       "Philosophical  Problems	 of  Space and Time."  Drawing upon
       the work	of the philosopher H. Bergmann,	he writes that	the
       commonsense,  everyday  experience  of  time  as	 a  flow of
       events -- as  distinct  from  the  reality  of  a  spacetime
       continuum -- is	entirely  a product of the consciousness of
       sentient	organisms.  He adds that the idea of "now"  has	 no
       basis  in  reality  apart  from the significance	imparted by
       such conscious experiences.   In	 other	words,	it  is	not
       *time*  that  flows; rather, *conscious awareness* flows, as
       it were,	through	time, giving time the appearance of motion.

       Our conscious awareness serves as the motion picture projec-
       tor, if you will, that makes the	film strips of time come to
       life  --	 that limits us	 to  a	three-dimensional  view	 of
       reality.	  Our  consciousness acts like the crest of a "vir-
       tual wave" of awareness moving through time.  Of	course,	 no
       mystical	 connotation  is  intended  regarding mind or cons-
       ciousness: all of  the  various	brain  states  and  sensory
       information  which underlie our consciousness must, also, be
       "already	 there,"  arrayed  in  spacetime.   Our	 subjective
       experience  is as if our	conscious awareness rippled through
       these brain states in a serial order.

		(This chapter to be continued in part 5.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (11/04/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

			   The Perpetual Moment

       This chapter will more fully explore an important aspect	 of
       our  immortality,  i.e.,	 the permanence	in spacetime of	our
       present lives.  The remaining chapters in this  series  will
       then  complete the overall concept by developing	a thesis of
       continued existence in the future, based	upon psychic  iden-
       tification through time.	 The goal of this series is to show
       that, even though science may lead us to	reject	the  tradi-
       tional  (religious)  idea  of a separate	duality	of mind	and
       body, we	need not conclude that death means personal annihi-
       lation.

       The intent is, in effect, to *redefine* the traditional idea
       of  "the	 soul"	for  the  21st	century	(or, at	least, that
       aspect of the word "soul" that means a vehicle of our immor-
       tality).	  Another way of looking at such a conclusion would
       be to say that the idea of a "soul" would be  invalid  in  a
       literal	sense,	but valid when used as a figurative, short-
       hand construction for the newly emerging	concept.

       Enough  information  about  the	nature	of  time  has  been
       presented  to  this  point  to  serve  as a foundation for a
       fuller understanding.  You will recall the  main	 conclusion
       of  the	previous  chapter:  the	ever-moving instant of time
       that we call "now" is only  special  because  our  conscious
       awareness  makes	 it  so; that apart from that awareness, no
       instant,	whether	past or	future,	would be any more  signifi-
       cant as to its time than	any other instant.

       Also introduced was the idea of a "virtual wave"	 of  aware-
       ness  that  flows  through  time.   All	of  us who view	one
       another as being	"of the	same time," who	 view  the  present
       and  past  from	the same frame of reference with respect to
       time, are, as it	were, carried along on the same	crest of  a
       single  wave  of	consciousness flowing through time.  And it
       was stressed that nothing mystical was intended in the usage
       of  the	word  "consciousness."	 For the neurophysiological
       brain  states  that  underlie  our  consciousness  are  also
       arrayed in spacetime -- every bit as much a part	of physical
       reality as are the various stages of change of any  physical
       object (such as trees and planets).  But	our awareness is as
       if it rippled across the	static movie film of time, bringing
       to life the movie of flowing time.

       With the	above perspective on time as background, let us	now
       explore	the  profound implications these ideas have for	the
       question	of "survival after death."

       The everyday reality of flowing time makes it seem that	the
       wave  of	 consciousness	of "our	time" is the *only* wave of
       consciousness there is.	Mass media, books, and history pro-
       fessors	reinforce that commonsense impression whenever they
       speak of	"historical events." We	believe	that what  we  view
       as the past is the *absolute past* of the universe, and what
       we view as the future is	the *absolute future*,	experienced
       by  none.  It seems incredible that there could be people in
       the future -- as	far ahead as we	care to	 project  (assuming
       we  haven't  yet	 annihilated  our-selves  and  the universe
       hasn't yet annihilated it-self) -- who are  experiencing	 as
       their  "now"  what  to us has not yet happened, and who view
       our present as the dead past.

       Yet, if this were not true, and there  were  only  a  single
       wave of consciousness passing through time, then	the picture
       of time that has	been painted here would	be false.  In  that
       case, there *would* be something	unique about the particular
       moving point of time that we call "now":	 for  none  of	the
       other  arbitrary	 "nows"	in the past or future would contain
       any consciousness.  And all the	remainder  of  spacetime --
	other than our "now" --	would be like the lifeless portions
       of a movie film that are	either ahead of	or behind the aper-
       ture  of	the projector.	The entire movie of spacetime would
       then be like a very long	film that is shown *only once*.

		   (Chapter to be continued in Part 7.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (11/10/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		     The Perpetual Moment (continued)

       No, the view of time as a movie shown  only  once  does	not
       seem  consistent	with the current physical model	of time.  A
       more appropriate	analogy	would appear to	 be  that  time	 is
       like  an	 infinitely  long movie	film threaded, all at once,
       through an infinitely  large  number  of	 movie	projectors.
       Each  projector	with  its  associated movie screen would be
       showing the same	movie as the others, but the screens  would
       be slightly out of phase	with one another.

       If one could view one of	the  earlier  screens,	he  or	she
       would  eventually  see scenes that were already visible on a
       later screen; and conversely, the later screens	would  have
       already	shown  what  was  appearing on the earlier screens.
       The infinite strip of movie film	can be compared	to  all	 of
       spacetime.  And each projector with its corresponding screen
       can be compared to a single virtual  moving  wave  of  cons-
       ciousness,  among  an infinite number of	such waves, flowing
       through time.  Such an analogy of an infinite number of mov-
       ing wavecrests of awareness is, of course, only a figurative
       model for a subjective experience of time.  The assumed per-
       petual awareness	at each	infinite moment	of time, throughout
       spacetime, would, it seems, exist in some type  of  timeless
       reality beyond time -- as does all of spacetime itself.

       However,	if the theory of parallel universes is correct (see
       parts 1 through 3 of the	series), then the movie	analogy	for
       the waves of consciousness must be again	modified.  We would
       still  have  an infinite	number of projectors, each with	its
       own movie screen.  But instead of a single  infinitely  long
       strip  of  film	threaded through all of	the projectors,	the
       effect (of the infinite branching of the	single film)  would
       be  of  an infinite number of different films, each threaded
       through its own movie projector.

       No two screens would show the same movie, although  many	 of
       the  movies  would be similar.  Many of the screens could be
       showing scenes from the same period of  time,  but  (because
       the  screens  would be offset "sideways"	in time) the scenes
       would be	slightly different  from  one  another.	  A  screen
       whose movie was offset earlier in time from some	of the oth-
       ers could, as in	the earlier analogy, be	showing	scenes that
       had  already  appeared  on  the	others;	but if we stayed to
       watch the movie,	we would discover that it had a	 "different
       ending,"	as it were.

       The model of spacetime as a single, unchanging strip of film
       is  simpler  than  that	of the infinitely branching film of
       parallel	universes.  But	since both models share	the concept
       of  an  infinite	 number	 of  waves of consciousness passing
       through time, they raise	similar	questions:  Why	 aren't	 we
       aware  of  the other "versions" of ourselves that exist for-
       ward, backward and (perhaps) sideways  in  time?	  And  with
       respect	to  parallel  universes, one would wonder why he or
       she is not aware	of the replications of	himself/herself	 in
       the other universes.  For according to the concept of paral-
       lel universes, every time there is a (probabilistic)  choice
       of  action,  the	 universe  branches  into as many different
       universes as there were possible	 courses  of  action.	And
       each  of	these universes	would contain a	replication of our-
       selves.

       Yet, we are never aware of more than one	 "us."	 The  other
       "versions"  of  us  are	separate persons, for all practical
       purposes; there is  no  physical	 contact  or  communication
       among  the  parallel  worlds, nor among the different times.
       That is,	if the "me" of an hour ago or a	week ago is "still"
       conscious  in  the past,	I am not aware of the fact.  So	the
       "me" in the past	is as much a different person,	as  far	 as
       everyday	 reality  is  concerned, as the	other "me's" of	the
       present,	in parallel worlds, would be.

		   (Chapter to be concluded in part 8.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (Henry Friedman) (11/16/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		     The Perpetual Moment (continued)

       The analogy of a	"wavecrest of consciousness" moving through
       time,  you  will	 recall,  referred not to a single person's
       consciousness, but  to  the  consciousness  of  everyone	 we
       regard  as belonging to our frame of reference of time.	Our
       commonsensical view of this wave	would include everyone	now
       alive  on our planet, since we view everyone whose existence
       we can know of as being of the same (and	only) time.  When a
       person  dies,  his or her consciousness is no longer part of
       that particular wavecrest.  But the wavecrest (of all  those
       whose times had been synchronous	with his) continues to move
       into the	future,	from the point of view	of  his	 survivors.
       To the person who has died, however, the	continued travel of
       the wave	of awareness to	which he formerly  belonged  is	 no
       longer really relevant.

       But at that point (after	our deaths), it	would  appear  that
       those other "us's" in our past -- which were irrelevant dur-
       ing our life --	would now be quite relevant indeed, because
       in  those  past "us's," in those	earlier	waves of conscious-
       ness, we	would survive.	It  would  be  as  if  that  sudden
       transfer	 of awareness into the past that was posited in	the
       previous	chapter	had actually occurred, and  we	then  found
       ourselves  back	in  the	 past, with total amnesia about	the
       future -- in fact, with no knowledge that anything had  even
       happened.   At  what  point in our past,	you ask. At any	and
       all points.  Take your pick!

       If you have followed the	series this far, it is likely  that
       you,  like  me,	do not believe in the traditional idea of a
       soul that leaves	the body at death, nor in the related  idea
       of  a reunion in	heaven with friends and	loved ones who have
       gone before you.	Each of	us has a time that belongs  to	him
       or  her.	 And,  the  thesis to be developed in the remaining
       chapters	notwithstanding, *that*	time is	the only time  that
       we will ever really be the same "us," the only time in which
       we will ever have the same environment, family, friends	and
       loved ones.  Therefore, if there	is to be a "reunion," it is
       in our present lives that it must occur.

       If the description, above, of the continuation of our  cons-
       ciousness  in  the  past	is valid, our *present*	life itself
       has represented a reunion with loved ones we have lost  once
       "before,"  in  our  future! And we could	be comforted in	our
       *present* grief for loved ones lost in  this  life,  in	the
       knowledge  that	such  "reunions"  continue  to occur in	the
       past.

       At this point in	the development	of these ideas,	the special
       significance  of	 the  concept of parallel universes becomes
       apparent. For without this concept, every wave of conscious-
       ness would be like every	other. And those different versions
       of ourselves in	the  past  would  be  fated  to	 experience
       exactly	the same joys and sorrows, successes and failures -
       - with no possibility of	growth or change.  In contrast,	the
       concept	of  parallel universes would allow each	"beginning"
       in the past to be "new":	there would be	no  reason  for	 my
       "new"  wave  of	awareness  to  thread the same path through
       spacetime as had	the wave I had "just left."

       Like waves of flashing lights traveling up a giant Christmas
       tree,  the  path	from bottom of my life to top would be dif-
       ferent each time.  And  each  "reunion"	in  the	 past  with
       friends and loved ones would be fresh and new, pregnant with
       the possibility of infinite variations, as my wave of  cons-
       ciousness weaved	its way	through	the many worlds	in time.

       Of course, the above ideas have a danger, even if  they	are
       valid.	For  they may encourage	a mentally unhealthful ten-
       dency to	"live in the past."  On	the other hand,	by  imbuing
       our  past with new meaning, the idea of the perpetual moment
       may aid us in making peace with that past, so  that  we	can
       live our	present	more fully.

			      END OF CHAPTER

		   (Series to be continued in part 9.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (11/22/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

			  What a Coincidence --

       Coincidences of one type	or another are frequent	occurrences
       for most	of us, and we take little notice of them. But occa-
       sionally, we experience a coincidence that seems	so striking
       and  improbable	that  we  feel	it  must have some meaning.
       "Meaningful coincidences" are of	 many  different  varieties
       and range from somber signs or premonitions of tragic events
       that later come true to,	possibly, a  series  of	 unexpected
       happy reunions with long-lost friends. But such coincidences
       satisfy two criteria: first, that the separate events do	not
       appear  to  have	a common cause,	and second, that the proba-
       bility of the events occurring together	by  chance  appears
       remote.

       You may be wondering at this point what coincidences have to
       do  with	immortality.  But if you'll bear with me, I'll soon
       explain why such	phenomena are, indeed, relevant.

       C. G. Jung, the pioneering psychologist of  the	unconscious
       mind,  studied  the  thinking of	philosophers throughout	the
       ages on the subject of meaningful coincidences. In an  essay
       in  1951	and a book in 1952 ("Synchronicity, an Acausal Con-
       necting Principle") Jung	stated his own hypothesis that such
       phenomena  are  a fundamental principle of the universe.	 He
       placed  "synchronicity,"	 his  term  for	 meaningful   coin-
       cidences,  on an	equal footing with such	fundamental laws of
       nature as spacetime, causality, and the conservation laws.

       In calling a series of  events  in  a  coincidence  acausal,
       Jung,  of  course,  did	not mean that the individual events
       were themselves without normal causes.  It is the improbable
       clustering  of  the  events  that is significant.  Jung also
       realized	that many coincidences	that  appear  statistically
       significant prove, upon closer scrutiny,	to be within normal
       chance.	For example, if	I had  a  rather  obscure  hobby --
	say,  collecting memorabilia about electric streetcars -- I
       would think it quite a coincidence if three  different  per-
       sons,  who  didn't  know	 of  my	 hobby,	 mentioned electric
       streetcars to me	in  a  single  day.   However,	if  I  then
       discovered  that	 they had all seen a TV-magazine feature on
       old streetcars, the experience would no longer  seem  "mean-
       ingful."	  Still, coincidences that appear highly improbable
       do occur	frequently, even if they are often  too	 subjective
       to  be  rigidly evaluated by statistical	methods.  This fact
       led Jung	to conclude that some universal	principle  must	 be
       at work.

       In addition  to	the  ordinary  types  of  improbable  coin-
       cidences,   Jung	  included  psychic  experiences,  such	 as
       telepathy, precognition,	and clairvoyance,  as  examples	 of
       synchronistic  events.  The  scientific concept of cause	and
       effect is based upon an orderly	arrangement  of	 events	 in
       time.   Jung reasoned that if an	event in the future somehow
       gives rise to an	event in the present (the  psychic  experi-
       ence),  the  phenomenon must be considered acausal, since it
       violates	the orderly progression	of time.

       Recalling the discussion	of  four-dimensional  spacetime	 in
       the  preceding chapters,	one would not be surprised to learn
       that Jung's contacts with Einstein deeply influenced Jung in
       developing  his	concept	 of  synchronicity.   Jung was also
       influenced by later developments	in quantum  physics,  which
       demonstrated  that  some	 processes in nature, especially at
       the subatomic level, are	more closely related to	probability
       than  to	causality.  In later attempts to explain synchroni-
       city to an uncomprehending  (or	incredulous)  public,  Jung
       also  wrote  that  he was influenced by the emerging concept
       that even causal	events must be considered to  have  a  sta-
       tistical	basis.

       Of course, probability only allows that the  highly  improb-
       able  is	 *possible*;  synchronicity, in	effect,	states that
       the highly improbable is	often to be *expected*.

		  (Chapter to be continued in part 10.)

       Note: The next  installment  will  be  delayed  until  early
       December	because	of the holiday and a business trip.

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (12/08/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		   What	a Coincidence --   (continued)

       Various nonpsychic methods of divining the future -- such as
       astrology,  "I  Ching,"	and  Tarot  cards -- were also con-
       sidered by Jung to be synchronistic.   Jung,  himself,  used
       astrology  as an	aid in his practice of clinical	psychology.
       He viewed the blending of the 12	signs of the  zodiac  in  a
       patient's  birth	chart as closely related to his	own concept
       of archetypal personality patterns.  The	term  "archetypes,"
       as used by Jung, refers to mythic images	and behavioral pat-
       terns from the "collective unconscious" of our species.	(In
       later  efforts  to  clarify  his	 concept  of the collective
       unconscious (see	"Man and His Symbols"),	Jung explained that
       he  had	concluded  that	 the  tendency	to  form archetypal
       images -- though	not the	specific  images  themselves --	was
       genetically transmitted.)

       Some modern astrologers quite agree with	the astronomers	who
       scoff at	the idea that the planets either cause or influence
       human events  (or  personality  traits).	  Like	Jung,  they
       believe	that  a	planetary configuration	that allows them to
       predict a series	of events is, itself, simply one event in a
       synchronistic   cluster.	  In   other   words,  astrological
       phenomena would also be another example of "meaningful coin-
       cidences."    The  planetary  configuration  would  no  more
       believed	to be the cause	of the predicted event than a clock
       is believed to cause the	sun to rise.

       A debate	about the possible validity  of	 astrology  is	not
       within  the scope of this series	(and would be heavy baggage
       indeed for my thesis to bear in the face	of a largely techn-
       ical  audience).	  But  although	none of	the ideas developed
       here depend upon	astrology, we shall see	 that  the  subject
       suggests	 interesting  and  useful ramifications.  In my	own
       fairly extensive	experience with	the subject, I	have  found
       that the	results	of a complete natal horoscope are very dif-
       ferent from the meaningless generalities	of  newspaper  sun-
       sign columns, are usually impressive (to	me) and	often star-
       tlingly accurate.  (Just	an example: I once  asked  a  young
       woman whose chart I had just completed whether she had had a
       particularly serious accident during a specific week several
       years  in the past.  I had just met her,	after a	relative of
       hers had	asked me to do the chart as  a	"blind	test."	She
       replied	that  she  had fallen off a horse that week and	had
       broken her back.) But I realize that a belief  in  astrology
       is anathema to most scientists, and it is not my	intent here
       to try to convince anyone otherwise.

       However,	 if  astrology	 *were*	  a   valid   synchronistic
       phenomenon,  that would be especially significant because of
       astrology's cyclical nature.   This  would  mean	 that  many
       coincidences  are not only statistically	meaningful, but	are
       also of a recurring nature.  Ancient civilizations  believed
       that the	seemingly eternal rising and setting of	the sun	and
       changing	of  the	 seasons  were,	 in  themselves,  proof	 of
       mankind's  immortality.	 And recurring cycles of meaningful
       coincidences *are* central to the concept  to  be  developed
       here, as	will be	further	explained in the next chapter.

       In the first chapter, two opposing philosophies of time were
       discussed (time as a process of change versus the philosophy
       of the "manifold").  Still another widely  held	concept	 of
       time, prior to the 19th century,	was that time was cyclical,
       i.e., that it would eventually repeat itself.   One  ancient
       Greek  belief, related to the above discussion of astrology,
       was that	events of any given day	would be  exactly  repeated
       every Great Year.  A Great Year would would have	passed when
       the planets, Sun, and Moon returned to the precise  relative
       configuration  as  had  existed	on  the	 day  in  question.
       Although	I do not want to be misunderstood as espousing such
       cyclical	views of time -- that time will	come full circle in
       an exact	repetition -- several interesting parallels between
       the concept to be developed in this series and those ancient
       concepts	will become apparent.

       When we call  a	coincidence  "meaningful,"  we	often  mean
       several different things: 1) that the coincidence was recog-
       nizable,	that is, that it was comprised of elements that	 we
       perceived  to be	related, 2) that the striking nature of	the
       coincidence appeared to	be  statistically  meaningful  (not
       within  normal  chance  expectancy), 3) that the	coincidence
       appeared	to carry an aura of  the  mysterious  or  spiritual
       (Jung's	favorite  word for this	is "numinous"),	and 4) that
       the experience had an inner personal  significance  for	us.
       Jung  strongly  emphasized  the	final two points and stated
       that all	synchronistic experiences involve archetypal images
       or  dreams.  While I am not personally convinced	that mythic
       archetypal symbols are always involved, this does seem often
       to be the case.

       I will relate one  such	personal  synchronistic	 experience
       that  occurred  several	years  ago,  a	few weeks before my
       mother's	unexpected death.  Shortly after falling asleep,  I
       had  wakened  with a start, thinking that someone had called
       out to  me  from	 outside.   I  immediately  felt  a  deeply
       depressing  awareness  of death -- not like a premonition of
       impending death,	but rather a full sense	of my mortality.

       The next	morning, after breakfast, I looked outside and	saw
       a  large	 reddish  songbird  lying dead on the deck, a short
       distance	from the bedroom.  It was one of a  beautiful  pair
       that  I	had greatly admired.  I	associated the bird's death
       with my experience during the night, with the thought that I
       had  perhaps sensed that	the bird lay out there in the dark-
       ness, dying.

       Later, after my mother's	death, I  recalled  that  Jung	had
       written that images of birds lighting on	a house	were arche-
       typal symbols of	death.	I also recalled	that I had  carried
       the  bird  through  the	house in a plastic bag to reach	the
       entrance, on the	floor below.  I	thought	of the	old  super-
       stition that if a bird flew into	one's house, someone in	the
       family would soon die.

       Despite its weakness as an example of striking  coincidence,
       the above synchronistic experience does qualify as a classic
       example of archetypal meaning.  But one of the problems with
       Jung's  contention  that	synchronicity ranks with the funda-
       mental laws of nature is	that experiences like mine,  above,
       seem too	subjective to reflect a	fundamental law	of nature.

       Is there	any scientific support for synchronicity,  or  must
       we  just	 dismiss the concept as	another	superstition, or as
       an unfortunate example of undisciplined eccentricity on	the
       part  of	 Jung?	 As  mentioned earlier in this chapter,	the
       exciting	realm of quantum physics, where	causality is subor-
       dinated to probability, seems to	offer such a beginning.

		  (Chapter to be continued in part 11.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (12/15/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		    What a Coincidence --  (continued)

       There are several classic  experiments  in  quantum  physics
       that demonstrate	the paradoxical	behavior of elementary par-
       ticles.	Gary Zukav writes that these experiments  have	led
       to  "Bell's  Theorem,"  which states, in	effect,	that if	the
       results of such experiments are correct,	then reality cannot
       be  as it appears to be.	 One such experiment involves pairs
       of particles which, after having	traveled too far  apart	 to
       communicate,  still appear to behave in a correlated manner.
       Zukav notes the relevance of the	concept	of synchronicity to
       this paradox, as	synchronicity is defined as strong correla-
       tion where there	is no causal relationship.  In other words,
       meaningful  coincidence	seems  to occur	even at	the quantum
       level of	reality.

       Quantum physicists have agreed that there are  a	 number	 of
       possible	 conclusions  that  can	 be reached concerning such
       paradoxes.  (The	conclusions would be  mutually	exclusive.)
       One  of the conclusions is that valid models of reality can-
       not be constructed.  Another involves the possibility of	 an
       absolute	 determinism (that constrained certain choices made
       by the observers	conducting the experiment).  One of the	two
       remaining  conclusions  contradicts relativity and indicates
       that communication faster than the speed	of  light  ("super-
       luminal") is possible.  (This would mean	that the two parti-
       cles in the experiment are *never* too far apart	to communi-
       cate.)  The  final  conclusion involves the concept of "many
       worlds,"	or parallel universes, as described earlier in this
       series.

       Physicist David Bohm, examining the  possibility	 of  super-
       luminal	communication, has suggested the idea of an "impli-
       cate order," a level of reality in which	all matter would be
       connected.   This  concept,  which  suggests  parallels with
       Eastern	religious  beliefs,  says,  in	effect,	 that	the
       apparent	separateness of	widely separated events	is an illu-
       sion.  He and physicist Jack Sarfatti have worked to  demon-
       strate that such	superluminal signaling is possible.

       Zukav explains that the ideas of	 Bohm  and  Sarfatti  would
       imply  that  particles that *ever* interacted would *always*
       continue	to affect one another, even when ordinary causality
       could  not  possibly  be	 involved.   If	 such  a concept is
       translated from the "micro" world of elementary particles to
       the  "macro"  world  of	everyday  things -- such as people,
       trees, cars, etc. -- it sounds very much	like synchronicity.

       The final possible conclusion  listed  above  regarding	the
       paradoxical  behavior of	subatomic particles involved paral-
       lel universes.  If applied to synchronicity, this  possibil-
       ity  appears  to	give a special role to human consciousness.
       What is suggested here is that synchronistic experiences	may
       serve  as signposts and switches, as it were, of	the branch-
       ing points of  our  parallel  universes.	  Such	experiences
       would  then  indicate  the  route traveled by our particular
       train of	awareness, as it threaded  its	way  through  these
       infinite	possibilities.

       When viewed from	the standpoint of parallel  universes,	the
       strangest coincidence loses its strangeness; for	a different
       universe	for *every* possibility	would exist at	each  point
       of  branching.	The  coincidence  would	simply show that we
       took the	particular path	that fulfilled	it.   In  his  book
       "Mysticism  and the New Physics," Michael Talbot	writes that
       synchronistic phenomena represent the  "reality-structuring"
       power  of  human	consciousness.	If consciousness plays some
       type of role in influencing the	paths  that  our  awareness
       weaves  through an infinity of parallel universes, then that
       fact would underscore the participatory role  of	 conscious-
       ness in the very	creation of reality.

       Either of the above two possible	explanations  (superluminal
       communications  or  parallel  universes)	 may  offer partial
       explanations for	synchronicity.	However, my  own  study	 of
       coincidences  of	 the  cyclical variety leads me	to conclude
       that no quasi-causal explanation	of such	 phenomena  can	 be
       complete.   For	some components	of synchronistic events, it
       appears that we can only	state that synchronicity *is*.	 By
       this  I	mean that in the domains of our	universe where ran-
       domness predominates over causality,  meaningful,  recogniz-
       able  patterns  of events occur -- for no apparent reason at
       all.

       In all great  works  of	art -- whether	literature,  music,
       painting,   etc.	-- we	find  repeating	 elements:  motifs,
       themes, variations, twists of plot.   These  repeating  ele-
       ments  serve  as	 a unifying principle for the work in ques-
       tion.  It seems that the	great drama of the  universe --	and
       especially  the	drama of conscious existence --	has somehow
       also not	been denied such artifices. Am I hinting  that	God
       did  it?	  Not  really, though I	don't deny the possibility.
       (Jung wrote that	he concluded that synchronicity	must result
       from countless "creative	acts" of God throughout	time.)	But
       such a conclusion would just be	anthropomorphizing  reality
       in  the	face  of  the  incomprehensible.  (Admittedly, syn-
       chronistic events do sometimes remind  one  of  "Kilroy	Was
       Here" signs.)

       As Lawrence LeShan writes ("Alternate Universes"), the prob-
       lem lies	in our tendency	to try to fit the world	into a sin-
       gle reality system, when, in fact, several  completely  dif-
       ferent  reality	systems	 are operating.	 Two of	the reality
       systems that LeShan describes have been discussed in  previ-
       ous  chapters  of  this	series:	 the  reality  of  everyday
       existence with its flow of  time	 (which	 LeShan	 calls	the
       "sensory	 modes	of  being")  and  the reality system of	the
       spacetime continuum.  The reality system	in which all things
       are  connected  and  in	which myth, magic and synchronicity
       operate,	LeShan calls the "mythic modes of being."

       It appears to me	that, so long as we  don't  examine  things
       too closely, that these different systems of reality usually
       mesh like the  rows  and	 columns  of  a	 crossword  puzzle,
       without	contradicting  one another.  For example, unless we
       travel at speeds	approaching the	speed of light,	 the  "time
       dilation" effects of special relativity are negligible.	And
       unless we do too	close an analysis, synchronistic events	can
       be  dismissed as	ordinary coincidences.	The classic experi-
       ments in	quantum	physics	may be an example of  "looking	too
       closely."

       In the next chapter, I will explain how the  reality  system
       of  synchronicity  operates  to help ensure our immortality.
       But to close this chapter, I will relate	 a  little  episode
       that  will  illustrate how an awareness of synchronicity	can
       sometimes allow one to predict the near future --  with	the
       aid  of	neither	 science,  futurism,  nor  astrology.	The
       secret, as you will see,	lies in	recognizing  the  beginning
       of  a  synchronistic  cluster of	events,	and then just using
       the old saying that "things come	in threes."

       About 10	years ago, I was trying	to rent	a car from an auto-
       mobile  dealer,	so that	their service department could work
       on my own car.  The young woman at the rental counter apolo-
       gized  that she couldn't	rent me	the car	because	my driver's
       license had expired.  I objected	that she must be  mistaken,
       but  then  was  embarrassed  to	discover that it had indeed
       expired.	 I had not received the	renewal	notice because of a
       change in my address.

       I then drove my own car to the nearest state  motor  vehicle
       office  to  apply  for the license renewal.  There the clerk
       gave me a form to complete and return to	him at the counter.
       When  I	later  handed  it  back	 to him, he scolded me very
       rudely for not following	his instructions correctly in  com-
       pleting the form.  What a morning!

       Later, at my office, I wondered	whether	 the  day  had	any
       additional  embarrassing	 incidents  in store for me.  There
       seemed to be a common thread between both incidents, in that
       they  both  involved  business transactions at counters with
       clerical	workers.  Although there was some causal  relation-
       ship  between  the  two	experiences, I felt that they still
       might be	the beginning of a synchronistic series.   If  this
       were so,	I reasoned that	the next incident would	most likely
       occur at	the company cashier counter, where personal  checks
       and business expense vouchers are cashed.

       However,	I decided that I was safe, because I didn't have to
       cash a check that day.  I would cheat fate, so to speak.

       The following morning, I	received an internal letter in	the
       company	mail.  It  was dated the preceding day and was from
       the supervisor of the cashier service.  The letter concerned
       a  personal,  third-party  check	 for  $15 that I had cashed
       several days earlier (my	wife had received it  in  repayment
       of  a  loan).  The check	had bounced, and the letter sternly
       warned that repeated occurrences	of bad checks would  result
       in suspension of	my check-cashing privileges!

			      END OF CHAPTER

       (Series to be continued in  part	 12,  in  which	 the  final
       chapter will begin.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (Henry Friedman) (12/22/83)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

			 -- There You Are Again!

       Many books and articles	about  reincarnation  have  related
       accounts	 of  persons  who  have	 supposedly  remembered	 or
       dreamed	about  past  lives,   or   have	  supposedly   been
       "regressed"  to	past  lives  under  hypnosis.	The  sudden
       acquisition of  special	knowledge  or  skills,	such  as  a
       foreign language, by such persons is often cited	as proof of
       reincarnation.  Investigation  sometimes	 reveals  that	the
       knowledge  believed  to	have  been remembered from a former
       life can	actually be explained by the fact that the  uncons-
       cious  mind can retain memories of fleeting experiences that
       the conscious mind has long forgotten.	However,  in  other
       instances  the  evidence	 seems	compelling that	the subject
       could not have acquired the special knowledge --	or  details
       of  the	life  of  a  person  who  died long ago	-- from	any
       encounter during	his or her own lifetime.

       (It is not within the scope of this  series  to	attempt	 to
       examine	or  evaluate  individual instances of such apparent
       regression.  However, admittedly, if investigation  revealed
       that  *all*  such  reported  occurrences	 could be explained
       without recourse	to the paranormal, then	the validity of	the
       hypothesis  to  be  developed here would	be doubtful.  It is
       also  not  within  the  scope  of  this	series	to  attempt
       *proofs*,  but  rather to suggest reasonable hypotheses that
       merit further investigation.   Of  the  many  "reincarnation
       books"  that  have  been	 written  (some	 of  which are pure
       trash), John Gribbin ("Timewarps") recommends the book "More
       Lives  Than One?" by Arnall Bloxham.  Gribbin cites an exam-
       ple from	this book that	involved  research  to	verify	the
       details	of  an	apparent former	life, details that couldn't
       have been known by the subject, since  they  were  literally
       unearthed by a subsequent archaeological	discovery.)

       In "Timewarps," John Gribbin suggests that in such instances
       the  person  is somehow *sensing* or *viewing* events in	the
       life of *another* person	in the past, rather than  remember-
       ing  his	or her own former life.	 According to this explana-
       tion, during dream and hypnotic states, the unconscious mind
       has  a latent capability	for transcending the limitations of
       ordinary	 three-dimensional  reality.   In  fact,   suggests
       Gribbin,	 subjects  under  hypnosis  could  probably just as
       easily been "progressed"	into the  future,  to  view  events
       from the	lives of persons who have not yet  been	born.

       If we accept Gribbin's explanation for such  "reincarnation"
       experiences, however, a puzzling	question still remains.	 If
       a person	who seems to have remembered a past life  is  actu-
       ally  *sensing*	scenes	from  the  past,  why  does such an
       experience center upon awareness	of a particular	 individual
       who  lived  in  the past?  Why would there be an	affinity to
       another person in the past that was so strong that the  sub-
       ject  actually  believed	that other person was himself, in a
       former life?

       Gribbin proposes	one possible explanation. Investigation	has
       apparently revealed that	persons	who have died violently	are
       more likely to be the objects of	such supposed reincarnation
       experiences  in future generations.  Gribbin suggests that a
       violent death might make	that person's life more	salient	 to
       a  future  "mental time traveler." However, this	explanation
       does not	seem adequate to account for such a strong affinity
       between two separate lives.

       It seems	that Gribbin was so intent on stating  the  differ-
       ences between his hypothesis of mental time travel and rein-
       carnation that he overlooked a possible similarity.   Assume
       the  validity  of  Gribbin's  belief  that  it is, at times,
       somehow possible	for us to view the past	in four-dimensional
       spacetime,  and that this ability explains some instances of
       apparent	remembering of past lives.  But	I propose the addi-
       tional  possibility  that  the person in	the present and	the
       person in the past, who share such a bond of sympathy across
       time, might be two very like personalities and two very like
       minds.

       Furthermore, just as reincarnation is  supposed	to  involve
       many  lifetimes,	 the  variation	 I'm  suggesting here could
       involve many different persons across the generations linked
       together	 by  a bond of "psychic	resonance." The	name I have
       given to	such presumed groupings	of persons is "time twins."
       Am  I  suggesting,  you	might ask, that	the person from	the
       past "lives on" in the person of	another	in the present	who
       feels attuned to	him -- in the person of	a time twin, who is
       a type of spiritual successor?  How would that  be  a  valid
       conclusion when I have already admitted that the	two persons
       are totally separate  --	and that there was no mind or soul,
       independent  of	the brain, that	could have transferred from
       one to the other?

		  (Chapter to be continued in part 13.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (Henry Friedman) (01/07/84)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		   -- There You	Are Again!  (continued)

       Of course, if instances of valid	"reincarnation experiences"
       were  common  instead  of rare, there might not be a problem
       with the	concept	of time	twins.	In that	case,  I  could	 be
       fairly  certain	that  after  my	death someone else would be
       born who	would know my whole  life,  and	 think	he  was	 me
       (reborn),  and  feel and	act just like me.  And so, it would
       appear reasonable that one would	then feel that	he  or	she
       would  indeed  experience  a  type  of "resurrection" in	the
       future.

       But given the fact that such instances of apparent remember-
       ing  are	rare (even assuming for	argument that some of these
       experiences are substantiated paranormal	events), where	are
       we  left?   For	the person who believes	in the conventional
       doctrine	of reincarnation, such apparent	rarity of recall is
       no  problem.  To	that person, *eventual*	remembering seems a
       certainty, as he	or she believes	that memory  resides  in  a
       soul,  not  in electrochemical waveforms	stored among neural
       synapses.  And  in  any	event,	he  believes  he  survives,
       absence	of  memory notwithstanding, because his	essence	has
       survived	and entered a different	body in	the future.  But to
       us non-soulists,	our supposed successor in the future cannot
       possibly	know us	by actual memory, and our  resurrection	 in
       the  future  would appear to depend upon	a highly improbable
       psychic event.

       To begin	to address some	of the above objections	to the con-
       cept  of	 time  twins,  let  me first state that	it operates
       largely in the mythic dimension (discussed in  the  previous
       chapter),  not  in the reality system of	everyday life.	And
       the mythic dimension is experienced largely by  the  uncons-
       cious,  not  the	conscious, mind	-- as evidenced	by the fact
       that the	archetypal  images  associated	with  synchronistic
       experiences  arise from the unconscious mind. This is not to
       say that	survival via time twins	is merely a fabrication	 of
       the  unconscious	 mind,	but  rather  that the reality would
       largely	be  *experienced*  at  the  unconscious	 level.	 Of
       course, if large	numbers	of people ever became interested in
       time twins, there would probably	be a resurgence	of interest
       in  hypnotic  regression.  If this were the case, the proba-
       bility of our more complete  "resurrection"  in	the  future
       would  be  improved,  as	our future time	twins endeavored to
       learn of	their psychic heritage from the	past.

       Given our knowledge about the unconscious, we  might  fairly
       readily accept the possibility of such intense psychological
       identification with another person, if the psi phenomenon of
       communication  through spacetime	could be corroborated.	For
       we know that  fairly  intense  unconscious  (and	 conscious)
       identification  occur  quite commonly, even when	the objects
       of such identification are very dissimilar  to  the  persons
       who  identify with them.	 If such were not the case, movies,
       novels and tv drama would not be	nearly	as  profitable	and
       popular as they are.

       Admittedly, the concept of time twins cannot  be	 considered
       valid  if  it  *makes  no apparent difference* in our lives.
       But if some of our conscious decisions  are  influenced	not
       just  by	 a combination of "nature and nurture,"	but also by
       unconscious psychic messages from  the  past  (and  future),
       from our	time twins, then the concept *would* be	meaningful.
       Examples	of such	possible  instances  of	 psychic  influence
       might  include 1) the ability of	child prodigies	to learn at
       a pace so rapid that the	learning seems to  outpace  by	far
       the  teaching  they  receive,  and  2)  the intense sense of
       direction or purpose that seems to drive	some  people,  even
       as  children.  Of course, this is not to	deny that the basic
       genetic talents and predispositions must	also be	present.

       But just	what is	meant by the statement,	 above,	 that  sur-
       vival via time twins operates mainly in the mythic dimension
       of reality?  A brief clarification of this point	 will  also
       serve  to show the relationship of the concept of time twins
       to the material introduced earlier in this series.

       In the reality system of	 everyday  life,  death	 means	the
       extinction  of  the person and the personality.	However, in
       our discussion of another reality system, the spacetime con-
       tinuum,	we  saw	 that  in  that	system of reality, the past
       "still" exists, the future  "already"  exists,  and  nothing
       that  has  ever	existed	 ever ceases to	exist.	Without	the
       reality of the spacetime	 continuum,  the  concept  of  time
       twins  would have no foundation;	for there could	then be	no,
       as it were, coexisting sets of persons across  the  ages	 of
       time to exert psychic influences	upon one another.  That	is,
       if I don't continue to survive in  the  past,  I	 cannot	 be
       "resurrected" through my	successor in the future.

       It is at	this point  that  the  third  reality  system,	the
       mythic  dimension,  is  relevant, in several different ways.
       First, the concept of time twins	requires that persons  very
       much  like  ourselves  appear  throughout time at reasonable
       (and possibly predictable) intervals.  This would, in  turn,
       appear to require the existence of the mechanism	of cyclical
       synchronicity that was  covered	in  the	 previous  chapter.
       Second, the existence of	a psychic mechanism that would per-
       mit a type of mental communication through time also appears
       to  depend  largely  upon  synchronicity.   (The	question of
       valid psi phenomena will	be discussed briefly  below.)	And
       finally,	 consider  the very idea that someone who no longer
       exists (in the present) can nevertheless	still exist (in	the
       present)	because	of some	type of	mental association: such an
       idea could only be valid	if there were a	reality	where  sym-
       bol  and	object of symbol were one.  That reality is, again,
       the mythic dimension.

       The unconscious mind, operating in the mythic  reality,	can
       resolve the apparent paradox of time twins: the same person,
       yet different persons.  For a major  characteristic  of	the
       unconscious  mind  is  the  free	 formation of many types of
       psychological and archetypal symbols.  And  the	unconscious
       mind  would not quibble about totally identifying with some-
       one who is, at the conscious level, a different person.	 In
       so  identifying with persons in the future and the past,	the
       unconscious mind	can  form  a  symbol  of  resurrection	and
       immortality.   And  in the mythic dimension, things that	are
       associated are no longer	separate (even though separated	 in
       space and time),	and symbols are	reality.

       In the reality of everyday life,	change	is  inexorable.	 In
       the  reality  of	the spacetime continuum, change	is an illu-
       sion.  And in the reality of the	mythic dimension, space	and
       time are	illusions.


	     (Chapter and series to be concluded in part 14.)

hsf@hlexa.UUCP (01/24/84)

		   (c) Copyright 1983 by Henry Friedman
	(Copying for personal use by users of net is authorized.)

		  -- There You Are Again!  (conclusion)

       In his book "Alternate Realities," Lawrence LeShan  examines
       how the idea of survival	after death would be viewed in each
       of several different reality systems.  He has no	 difficulty
       with  everyday reality (the "sensory modes"), in	which death
       clearly means the end of	our personal existence.	 The  real-
       ity  of	the  spacetime	continuum  (which  LeShan terms	the
       "clairvoyant modes of being") is	clearly	favorable  to  some
       type  of	survival, and he has no	difficulty there.  But when
       he comes	to the	mythic	dimension  (the	 "mythic  modes	 of
       being"),	 LeShan	 admits	to being somewhat puzzled about	the
       implications of	this  reality  system  for  survival  after
       death.

       When I first read "Alternate Realities,"	in  the	 summer	 of
       1978, I believed	I might	have the answer	to LeShan's puzzle,
       as I had	been formulating the  concepts	presented  in  this
       series  for several years.  This	led me to consider formally
       developing the material.	 But the final motivation  came	 in
       1980,   after  reading  John  Gribbin's	"Timewarps,"  which
       offered support for my belief that reincarnation	experiences
       were  related  to psychic communication through time.  (How-
       ever, Gribbin did not extend that idea  into  a	concept	 of
       actual personal survival	after death.)

       So that is a bit	of background about how	this material  came
       to be.  But before the series can be concluded, there is	one
       additional question that	was mentioned above that still must
       be  addressed:  the question of mental communication through
       time.  For if such ESP phenomena	do not really  occur,  then
       there  can  be  no  valid  basis	 for time twins, the mythic
       dimension notwithstanding.

       Serious research	in the field of	parapsychology to date	has
       apparently  left	 the  issue  of	the validity of	ESP largely
       unresolved.  Although many experiments have  yielded  highly
       favorable  statistical  evidence	 for  ESP,  the	results	are
       often not consistently repeatable.  (There  is,	however,  a
       question	of whether consistent repeatability is a fair stan-
       dard for	such research.)

       Most of us *are*	probably aware of the campaigns	 that  have
       been  underway  for  some  time	in  the	 popular scientific
       literature  attempting  to  completely  discredit  all  such
       research	 and  researchers.   These  attacks  seem  to  stem
       largely from what  is  perceived	 as  the  psi  researchers'
       presumptuous  behavior  in  insisting  on  the right to join
       august scientific associations.	Also, fairly recent  highly
       publicized  instances are alluded to in which such research-
       ers were	the victims of psychic scams perpetrated by some of
       their subjects.	The critics claim that such incidents prove
       that psi	researchers are	too biased in favor of the  subject
       to do objective tests.

       But to some people, such	arguments are  academic.   Although
       our  personal  psychic  experiences may be too subjective to
       prove anything, many of us -- though not	 "psychics" -- have
       on  occasions had apparent psi experiences that were person-
       ally compelling.	 As long as it appears	that  the  jury	 is
       still  out  on the question of scientific evaluation of psi,
       some of us will decide the issue	for  ourselves	based  upon
       such personal experiences (or, in many cases, weigh the evi-
       dence and reject	psi as nonsense).

       An earlier version of this series expressed the opinion that
       if  ESP	phenomena  were	purely synchronistic, the phenomena
       might then not occur regularly enough to	support	the concept
       of time twins.  However,	I have since developed doubts about
       that conclusion,	and now	question the present usefulness	 of
       speculating  about  quasi-,  convoluted,	 or  reverse-causal
       explanations  for  ESP.	 Even  if  the	evidence  for	the
       existence of ESP	phenomena ever appears incontrovertible, we
       may nevertheless	do little better in explaining why than	 to
       accept  ESP as an intrinsic quality of the mythic mode, that
       is, as synchronistic phenomena (which, in  turn,	 as  stated
       previously,  cannot  be completely explained). Nevertheless,
       for the sake of a more complete discussion, I  will  briefly
       review some of the more common quasi-causal explanations	for
       ESP phenomena.

       One explanation for ESP is basically the	same as	the  possi-
       ble  explanation	for synchronicity that was discussed in	the
       preceding chapter: the ESP experience merely indicates  that
       one's  awareness	 has  taken  the  path	among  the parallel
       universes that fulfills it.  The	two personal  apparent	ESP
       experiences  which  I recall the	most vividly could possibly
       be explained by such "track switching."

       The first ESP experience	occurred when I	was a child at sum-
       mer  camp.  We were having dinner in the	dining hall, seated
       at round	tables by  cabin  group.   I  noticed  one  of	the
       campers,	 a girl	of my age, returning from across the dining
       hall to her table, which	adjoined mine.	 I  visualized	(or
       fantasized?) that she would catch the front of her shorts on
       the pole-back of	a chair, across	from me,  as  she  threaded
       her  way	 between  the  tables, ripping her shorts open.	And
       that is exactly what then happened.  (Believe  me,  I'm	not
       trying  to  spice  up  a	 dull manuscript with some softcore
       kiddie porn; this really	did happen!)

       The second experience occurred some years later.	After read-
       ing  a  book  about  mental  telepathy,	I decided to try an
       experiment.  As the book	had instructed,	 I  visualized	the
       other  person,  my  "girlfriend," at the	other end of a long
       tube.  For several minutes, I  repeatedly  implored  her	 to
       telephone  me.	Now, back in those days	(don't make me con-
       fess how	far back!), it was not acceptable for a	young woman
       to  telephone  a	 young man; and	she had	never done so.	But
       within five minutes, she	did telephone me.   Later,  I  felt
       very  guilty  about  using  such	"psychic manipulation,"	and
       vowed never to do anything like that again.   (Besides,	the
       book  issued the	most dire warnings about the use of psychic
       powers for "evil	purposes.")

       Another attempt to explain ESP is based upon  neuropsycholo-
       gist  Karl  Pribram's hypothesis	of holographic memory (that
       human memory is stored in the form of wave interference pat-
       terns).	 When  this  idea  is  combined	with a variation of
       Bohm's "implicate order"	 (discussed  earlier),	interesting
       ramifications   are  possible.	This  explanation  for	ESP
       presumes	that the entire	universe and the spacetime  contin-
       uum  are	 themselves  projected,	 as  it	were, from a super-
       reality,	existing in the	form of	wave interference  patterns
       (analogous  to  a  3-D laser hologram).	And since the brain
       would be	naturally  adept  at  processing  holograms,  there
       would  then  presumably be nothing unusual about	the brain's
       ability to translate information	stored in  the	holographic
       super-reality.

       A third attempt to explain ESP is based upon  a	combination
       of  general  relativity	and  quantum  physics: the "quantum
       gravity"	effect.	 General relativity states that	gravity	 is
       not really a "force acting at a distance," but is rather	the
       result of the warping of	spacetime  itself,  caused  by	the
       presence	 of  massive bodies.  In other words, gravity would
       be  considered  a  geometric  phenomenon.   The	"Heisenberg
       uncertainty  principle" of quantum physics would	permit very
       large masses to spontaneously generate without violation	 of
       the  conservation  laws,	 so long as the	newly formed matter
       disappears in an	extremely minute time interval.	  Combining
       those two scientific laws, physicists speculate that, in	the
       world of	 extremely  short  time	 intervals,  space  is	not
       smooth,	but  is	spongy and full	of "wormholes,"	as a result
       of the gravitational effect of such spontaneously  generated
       matter.

       Some  parapsychologists	speculate  that	 such	"wormholes"
       through	spacetime could	serve as communication channels, as
       it were,	for ESP	phenomena.  This would be analogous, on	the
       psychological  level, to	the speculation	by some	astrophysi-
       cists that "black holes"	may serve as physical  gateways	 to
       other  times or places in our universe, or even to different
       universes.

       The final possible explanation for ESP  that  will  be  men-
       tioned  here  depends  upon  the	existence of a hypothetical
       elementary particle called  the	"tachyon."  Although  rela-
       tivity  forbids anything	from *reaching*	the speed of light,
       it would	not be inconsistent with the existence of a  parti-
       cle  that has always, from birth, traveled *faster* than	the
       speed of	light.	Some  scientists  postulate  that  tachyons
       exist, although they have not yet succeeded in finding them.

       A particle that traveled	faster than light would	 appear	 to
       be traveling *backward* in time.	 And some parapsychologists
       speculate that interaction with tachyons	in the brain  might
       explain ESP phenomena.

       Despite the above attempts to explain ESP, most serious	psi
       researchers  spend  their  time in experiments that may lend
       statistical support to ESP, not in trying to explain why	ESP
       occurs.	Such researchers will usually only note	that modern
       physics,	by showing that	our view of reality is	incomplete,
       leaves room for the existence of	ESP.

       To conclude this	series,	I will use an analogy from  elemen-
       tary  astronomy.	  One of your earliest grade school science
       lessons may have	been that the planets  are  held  in  their
       orbit  around the sun by	a balance between centrifugal force
       and the pull of gravity.	 In college, a physics teacher	may
       have  lectured  that there really is no such thing as a cen-
       trifugal	force that pulls outward on the	planets.  The  idea
       of  centrifugal	force is a figurative construct	to simplify
       the effect of the *inertia* of the moving planet.

       Still later, you	may have  studied  general  relativity	and
       learned	that Newton's idea of gravity as a "force at a dis-
       tance" is not literally correct.	 As discussed  above,  Ein-
       stein  showed  that  gravity is a result	of a warping of	the
       geometry	of spacetime.  In following their elliptical orbits
       around  the  sun,  the planets are actually traveling in	the
       closest path to a straight line in warped spacetime.

       But just	because	we found that our old ideas about astronomy
       were  not literally true, we didn't fear	that the solar sys-
       tem would suddenly become unhinged.  For	one thing,  we	had
       the  direct evidence of our senses that the earth still pro-
       ceeded on its usual course.  And	 furthermore,  science	had
       substituted  new	 explanations  for the old --  explanations
       that still provided for our familiar solar system.

       But it is quite a different story with respect  to  the	old
       concept	of  the	soul that formerly ensured our immortality.
       The loss	of this	concept	leaves us to face a cold new  real-
       ity: our	personal annihilation at death.	 Only the discovery
       of new concepts to replace the old could	restore	our  belief
       in immortality.

       The purpose of  this  series  has  been	to  try	 to  arouse
       interest	 in whether such new perspectives are possible,	and
       also, to	suggest	some directions	in which  the  answers	may
       lie.  If	we continue the	search,	we may indeed find that	our
       immortality is cradled in the very fabric of space and time.

			      END OF SERIES

       (Any and	all comments and critiques of this series would	 be
       most  welcome,  either  by  mail	or on the net.	Even if	you
       just write to say how many of these articles you	have  read,
       I  would	appreciate it very much.  Would	a new generation of
       readers several years down the road be  interested  in  this
       material?  If so, should	I present it any differently then?)