wex@ittvax.UUCP (Alan Wexelblat) (07/25/83)
An answer to Paul Torek, and an introduction to Kant: For openers (this one's going to be long, gang), let me request that we keep this to net.philosophy. Paul is currently posting to net.politics as well, which I would like to avoid. Second, I would like to hear his reviews of the Kant books he mentioned since I have not read them. The texts used in my classes were all essays written by Kant himself (with various translators). Kant sets himself the goal of constructing a "rational" system of morality. This is his answer to the 'intuitionalist' systems of morality that preceded him. He beleived (as do most moral philosphers) that a system of morality must be universally applicable. In order to do this, he attempted to base his system on a sense of duty (action governed by a principle). The principle on which he wished to base morality was stated thus: "Maxims of conduct are such that they can be willed to be universal laws." In order to determine if a principle or act you are considering is a 'maxim of conduct,' apply the "universal laws test." If your principle passes the test, it can be considered a maxim. (Kant also raises issues of freedom and rationality -- he implies that rationality is necessary for freedom, and says that freedom is necessary for morality. I do not want to tackle these thorny questions here. They are not crucial to my arguments against Kant.) The universal laws test is a four step process. It involves asking yourself four questions. To each, an affirmitive answer must be given (we assume that the test-taker is not fooling himself). If a single negative is encountered, the principle or act is not a maxim of conduct. The questions are: 1) if I desire X*, does everyone desire X? 2) Does everyone want X? 3) Does everyone always want X? 4) What if this were a law of nature? {* footnote: to say "I desire X" is to say the following: if X is a material good, then I wish to possess it. If X is a possible situation, then I desire that that situation should come to pass. If X is an action, then I desire to perform that action. If X is a boolean, then I desire X to be true. end footnote} Kant, of course, has a great deal more to say on the subject. However, all his positions stem from this one bit of philosophy, and I shall concentrate on it. Several questions arise at this point: Even if the universality test works, does it provide a necessary and sufficient basis for morality? Kant assumes that principles guide all actions; is this so? Even if one passes the first three parts of the test, one may not want everyone to act on this principle. Let us consider a plausible example (call it example 1): - I want a limited good X. - My reasons for wanting X are logical and moral. - I cannot criticize others for wanting X. - But since the supply of X is limited, I do not want others to desire it. Therefore, I will fail step four of the test, even though my desire is perfectly moral (by my intuition). This leads us to a questioning of the fourth step of the test: Why should anyone worry about the application of a maxim as a universal law? In other words, why should my morality be determined by considerations of a Utopian world? Kant attempts to justify step four by claiming that only by adherence to it can one live up to one's obligations as a rational and free person. He does not provide any logical basis for this step, merely a claim. But step four can lead to irrational results, directly contradicting Kant. Look at the community of altruists; they pass the test with flying colors, yet in implementation, they are ludicrous! Let us take up another challenge to Kant (call it example 2): You are the captain of a rescue boat. Because of circumstances, you are faced with a choice of rescuing only one of two people. There is not time to rescue both, and neither rescue poses any dangers for anyone. You have no responsibilities other than the ones detailed above. One of the people whom you can rescue is a person you love, the other is a total stranger. Whom do you save? Posed this question, people will automatically answer "the loved one." It seems to be common sense, and you would think less of the person who rescued the stranger. This is a concept which is strongly embedded in what is called intuitive morality*. Yet there is no way to capture this in the Kantian system. In actuality, one could construct a maxim which says that "In situations like the above, one should save the loved one." But this is clearly ludicrous! If your loved one said that s/he rescued you because of a rational principle you would be upset. You expect him/her to say that s/he rescued you because of who you are! But Kant explicitly ignores this facet of morality. Now we come to an interesting point: What are the possible consequences of running the world in a Kantian way? I will use one final example to make this point (call it example 3): Let us suppose that I have a large sum of money, and that I will shortly die. I have no living relatives. Now, the world being what it is, I see two things I would like to do with my money: I could donate it to CARE to help alleviate third world starvation, or I could use it to build a new facility onto the library to help them preserve old books which are decaying. Now I apply the Kantian test to each of the principles to see which one I should do, and I discover that it would be a wonderful thing if everyone gave money to alleviate starvation, and a really useless thing to have lots of old-book-preservation facilities. So the books rot. Now, how many of you are going to give all your money to CARE when you die? Very few, I'll bet. (If you are giving it to your children, Paul, see example 2, above.) Do you consider yourself immoral for not doing so? Obviously not. Kant fails completely to capture peoples' intuitions on topics like this. Yet he claims that his moral system is a "rational" one. I beleive that I have demonstrated clearly that it is not. --Alan Wexelblat decvax!ittvax!wex