okeefe.r.a.@edxa@sri-unix.UUCP (10/14/83)
From: RICHARD HPS (on ERCC DEC-10) <okeefe.r.a.@edxa> The resolution of the paradox lies in realising that "cheap apartments are expensive" is not contradictory. "cheap" refers to the cost of maintaining (rent, bus fares, repairs) the apartment and "expensive" refers to the cost of procuring it. The fully stated theorem is \/x apartment(x) & low(upkeep(x)) => difficult_to_procure(x) \/x difficult_to_procure(x) => high(cost_of_procuring(x)) hence \/x apartment(x) & low(upkeep(x)) => high(cost_of_procuring(x)) where "low" and "high" can be as fuzzy as you please. A reasoning system should not conclude that cheap flats don't exist, but rather that the axioms it has been given are inconsistent with the assumption that they do. Sooner or later you are going to tell it "Jones has a cheap flat", and then it will spot the flawed axioms. [I can see your point that one might pay a high price to procure an apartment with a low rental. There is an alternate interpretation which I had in mind, however. The paradox could have been stated in terms of any bargain, specifically one in which upkeep is not a factor. One could conclude, for instance, that a cheap meal is expensive. My own resolution is that the term "rare" (or "rare and highly sought") must be split into subconcepts corresponding to the cause of rarity. When discussing economics, one must always reason separately about economic rarities such as rare bargains. The second assertion in the syllogism then becomes "rare and highly sought objects other than rare bargains are (Zadeh might add 'usually') expensive", or "rare and highly sought objects are either expensive or are bargains". -- Ken Laws ]