[net.ai] Seminar announcement

gary@rochester.UUCP (Gary Cottrell) (02/22/84)

From: Gary Cottrell  <gary>







                University of Cottage Street
                    Dept. of Dog Science
                     55 Cottage Street
                 Rochester, New York 14608


                          SEMINAR


                 Saturday, 25 February 1984
                       55 Cottage St.
                         9:00 p.m.

                          Speaker
                    Garrison W. Cottrell
                University of Cottage Street

                           Topic

       "New Directions in Connectionist Dog Modeling"

     Further work has been done in the last year on the con-
nectionist (spreading activation) formalism for modeling the
generic dog (see Dog: A Canine  Architecture,  Cottrell  81;
Toward  Connectionist  Dog Modeling, Cottrell 82). We extend
the model to  investigate  sub-primate  language  use.  This
greatly  simplifies  the  task  of language study, since the
language generation system consists of little more than

                  S->"arf"|"rough"|"bark"

thereby circumventing the transformational theories of Chom-
sky  and his gang of leftist thugs. Our first resuIt is that
the language comprehended by the generic dog is

                      S-> {"no"}{N|V}

with  no  lexical  items  in  common  with  the   generation
language.   We  can therefore study the comprehension system
as totally independent of the  generation  system.  In  this
impoverished  domain,  we  may  study lexical access to word
information independent of any surrounding  sentence  struc-
ture.  In particular, we may study the well known effects of
pragmatic context on comprehension. For example, the  string
"Call  the  elevator, JellyBean" when uttered in the context
of "no elevator", causes the dog  to  jump  on  the  nearest
wall,  whether it has a button or not.(1) Therefore, in this
language domain, the appropriateness of the context is actu-
ally  computed by the speaker, while the hearer must make do
with whatever resources are available  to him at  the  time.
The second result is that the dog has few internal resources
available (little brain).

     We intend to put the model to a practical test by show-
ing that previous "impoverished phoneme" naming verification
experiments, which showed that the dog accepted "whiskey" as
"biscuit"  in  the  context  of  a  biscuit, generalize to a
forced choice paradigm, i.e.,  where whiskey is actually one
of  the  choices, the generic dog will still choose the bis-
cuit, showing that the problem is one of an inadequate world
knowledge frame (no brain). The materials remaining from the
test will be served to observers, in the interest of gaining
introspective   intuitions  as  to  the  nature  of  such  a
decimated world view.

_____

1. Such a result also shows that the lexicon of the dog  may
be collapsed from previous estimates of 20-30 words to a few
modifiers of the current state.  For  example  "get  in  the
back"  (of  the  car)  when uttered in the office causes the
animal to get up and move.  Giving any credence to the  look
of  confusion  on his face is surely the result of anthropo-
morphizing.


-------------------------------------------------
This was a recent party announcement here. I was encouraged to share it with
the world at large. Hope you enjoy it.
gary cottrell

gary@rochester.UUCP (10/14/84)

From: Gary Cottrell  <gary>




                     University of Cottage Street
                         Dept. of Dog Science
                          55 Cottage Street
                      Rochester, New York 14608


                               SEMINAR


                      Saturday, 20 October, 1984
                            55 Cottage St.
                              9:00 p.m.

            _M_o_d_e_l_l_i_n_g _t_h_e _I_n_t_e_n_t_i_o_n_a_l _B_e_h_a_v_i_o_r _o_f _t_h_e _D_o_g

                         Garrison W. Cottrell


          Many of us, while  out  for  a  stroll,  have  had  the
     experience   of  observing  a  dog  trotting  along,  alone,
     obviously _g_o_i_n_g _s_o_m_e_w_h_e_r_e.  This raises many questions, such
     as, "Where is he going?", "Why is he going there?", "Will it
     be more fun than where I'm  going?",  and  so  forth.   Such
     questions  motivate  us  to  postulate the existence of (and
     hence the efficacy of  further  study  of)  the  intentional
     behavior of the dog[1].

          We propose a highly parallel, neurologically  plausible
     model  of  dog  behavior  based  on  a connectionist (neural
     network) implementation  of  a  subset  of  Reiter's  (1980)
     Default  Logic, as reported in Cottrell (1984).  As outlined
     in that paper, there is a well specified mapping of  default
     rules  to  connectionist  network  fragments  that implement
     those rules, with the benefit that the network  operates  in
     real  time  by  continuously updating the truth value of all
     predicates in parallel[2] (thus  making  Doyle's  work,  and
     perhaps  Doyle  himself,   superfluous).    Currently,   the
     implementation   only   allows   inference  rules  with  one
     universally quantified variable.  While inadequate for  many
     purposes,  we  claim  that  this  is  all  we  need  for dog
     modelling, since it appears that dogs can only  think  about
     one thing at a time anyway[3].  In this work we  reinterpret
     ____________________
        [1]Grembowitz (1982) proposed a model  of  the  cat,  but
     only  handled  the case of the cat tripping on catnip, cata-
     tonically staring at the wallpaper for hours  with  sporadic
     leaps  into  space.   This  simple  behavior  was  elegantly
     modeled by the composition of only two standard UNIX  calls,
     random(3c) and sleep(1).
        [2]The observant reader will recognize a certain similar-
     ity to British Motor Corporation's  oft-lamented  experiment
     of  shoehorning an Austin Healey six cylinder engine into an
     MGB.  Early results support the contention that our  bastard
     child of a similar "marriage made in hell" will be more suc-
     cessful.
        [3]It is interesting to note that the set of things a dog
     can think about as noted in "Dog:  A  Canine  Architecture",
     Cottrell  (1981)  may  be _f_i_n_i_t_e and limited to food, squir-
     rels, and other dogs.  Further, the dog we have studied  ap-
     pears  to only have three responses to other dogs, depending
     on their sex.





     Reiter's  default  inference  rules  as  precondition-action
     behavior rules.  An example behavioral rule is:

                                Chase(x)
                         -----------------------
                         Moving(x) : Squirrel(x)


          An  English  interpretation  of  this  rule   is,   "if
     something  is  moving,  and  we  don't have evidence that it
     isn't a squirrel, then chase it." This models  the  observed
     behavior  of  Jelly Bean chasing a paper bag.  The real time
     behavior of our implementation captures his stopping when it
     turns  out  not  to  be  a  squirrel,  since that blocks the
     inference of Chase(x), which then  slowly  decays,  much  as
     Jelly  Bean  slows  to  a  confused halt.  (As a simplifying
     assumption, we ignore his subsequent pretense of not  having
     been  chasing  it  at  all.)  Of  course,  we  still have to
     determine whether there might still be  some  peanut  butter
     and  jelly in the bag, but this can be easily handled by the
     addition of more rules.  Note that since we are  building  a
     model  of  behavior, the consequent of the rule is an action
     (Chase(x)), not  an  addition  of  the  useless  information
     Squirrel(x) to the already overtaxed knowledge base[4].

          We have a grandiose long term research  plan  to  model
     the  entire  mind  of  the  dog,  which  will generate grant
     proposals _a_d _n_a_u_s_e_u_m.  One of the new tools we plan  to  use
     in  this  research  is  the  previously unnoticed ability to
     access the goal structures of the dog through measurement of
     tail wagging (for a discussion of some other aspects of tail
     wagging, including tail recursion,  see  "The  Dog  Papers",
     Benson  & Sloan (1984)).  We claim that tail wagging will do
     for dog modelling research what reaction times have done for
     psychology.   For  example,  we  can  use  this technique to
     assess the goal priorities of the dog.  If we  ask  "do  you
     want to go out?" we get a vigorous wagging response, whereas
     if we ask, "do you want to stay?", we get no  tail  wagging.
     Further,  we  can map out all of the levels of the system by
     studying  the  _t_i_m_e  _c_o_u_r_s_e   of   the   wagging   behavior.
     Demonstrations  of  the  the  time  course  of  the  wagging
     response will be provided.











     ____________________
        [4]As  evidence  that the knowledge base is already full,
     one only needs to note that when Squirrel(x)  holds,  and  x
     climbs a tree, the dog repeatedly attempts to climb the tree
     by jumping on the trunk, even though this tactic  has  never
     been observed to succeed.





(Copies of the troff source available on request)
gary cottrell (allegra or seismo)!rochester!gary (USENET)
	gary@rochester (ARPA)