LAWS@SRI-AI.ARPA (12/08/84)
From: AIList Moderator Kenneth Laws <AIList-REQUEST@SRI-AI> AIList Digest Saturday, 8 Dec 1984 Volume 2 : Issue 173 Today's Topics: Journals - LISP Papers & Computational Intelligence, Brain Theory - Caenorhabditis Elegans, Cognition - Infant Amnesia & PBS and The Brain, Seminars - Speech & Language & Memory & Math Representation (CSLI), Conference - Intelligent Systems and Machines ---------------------------------------------------------------------- Date: Fri 7 Dec 84 15:16:31-PST From: Michael Georgeff <georgeff@SRI-AI.ARPA> Subject: Journals for LISP papers I wish to submit a paper on a new and efficient method for implementing funargs in LISP (currently an SRI Tech Note) to an appropriate journal. Anyone know of any GOOD journal that publishes papers on programming languages and implementations?? Michael Georgeff. ------------------------------ Date: Thu 6 Dec 84 16:58:08-PST From: C.S./Math Library <LIBRARY@SU-SCORE.ARPA> Subject: Computational Intelligence--New Journal Computational Intelligence/Intelligence Informatique is a new journal which will publish in English/French high-quality original theoretical or experimental research in computational (aritificial) intelligence. The editors are Nick Cercone/Simon Fraser University and Gordon McCalla/Univer. of Saskatchewan. Editorial board includes L. Bolc, A. Mackworth, A. Ortony, R. Perrault, E. Sandewall, A. Sloman, n. Sridharan, D. Wilkins etc. Subscription rates: U.S. $85 institutional, $47 personal. It will be a quarterly with the first issue to be available February 1985. It will be published by the National Research Council of Canada and sponsored by the Canadian Society for Computational studies of intelligence. For more information: Distribution, R-88 (Computational Intelligence), National Research Council of Canada, Ottawa, Ontario, Canada, K1A OR6. Special rates for members of Canadian Societies. Manuscripts should be addressed to the editors, Computational Intelligence, Computing Science Department, Simon Fraser University, Burnaby, British Columbia, Canada, V5A 1S6. I will be ordering this title for the Math/CS Library. [...] Harry Llull ------------------------------ Date: Thu 6 Dec 84 12:01:07-CST From: ICS.DEKEN@UTEXAS-20.ARPA Subject: brains, kludges, and elegance The most substantial evidence of brain kludgery or lack thereof curiously resides in the structure (completely mapped) of a nematode named ... "elegant." Caenorhabditis elegans has 302 neurons of 118 different types, which make about 8000 synapses in total (each process synapses with about 50% of its neighbors). The lineage of every one of these cells is known, and the process by which neurological structures are formed may well seem, to a computer scientist, a kludge. Bilateral symmetry is not produced, for example, in the "logical" mirror-image development of a single precursor. The word "kludge," though, carries a pejorative connotation which seems inappropriate - there are multiple forces and priorities at work. (One might similarly feel that "kludge" is not the right word to describe democracy relative to totalitarianism.) A better word, which may mean something to biologists and others outside the hacker's ken, might be "fossiliferous," used to describe any system (program or biological organism) which carries along the baggage of its own trial-and-error evolution. As Sulston, White, Thomson, and Schierenberg put it: "... the perverse assignments, the cell deaths, the long-range migrations - all the features which could, it seems, be eliminated from a more efficient design - are so many developmental fossils." (There is a three-part series on C. elegans in Science of 22 Jun, 6 Jul, and 13 Jul). ------------------------------ Date: Thu, 6 Dec 1984 01:59 EST From: MINSKY%MIT-OZ@MIT-MC.ARPA Subject: Infant Amnesia V2 #165 The general evidence for infant memories is pretty poor. For one thing, as Ken Laws points out, there is something mighty suspicious about those handfuls of memories each person claims. In psychiatry some of these are called "screen memories". A very common feature is to remember some scene, sort of "eidetically" -- but on questions, the subject very often sees itself right in the center of the stage! Since this is impossible, obviously, the conclusion is that the memory is a construct. What's worse, with careful questioning, one usually finds that the memory has indeed been rehearsed, as Ken remarks, perhaps periodically. Presumably it has been reconstructed in the process, too -- and can hardly be called a memory, but rather, an elaborated theory or fantasy. Finally, even more careful questioning is revealing: how do you know that this was when you were three years old? Oh, I'm sure of it. It was the day my dog was run over. An innocent clue like that most likely points to an incident of Freudian magnitude; a loss or death, itself rehearsed perhaps for months, and then, unconsciously, for all the rest of one's life. In any case it is silly to haggle over the sharpness of the cutoff of infantile amnesia. I like theories like this: our experience is first encoded in rather stupid ways; a square is seen as a line attached to another line attached to another line, etc. Like an early assembly-language. Later, a square is represented as "closed path of equal lines" and, later, orthognal pairs of parallels, etc. -- going to Fortrams to Pascals to LOGs to SMALLTalks to who-knows-what. The representatins and their interpreters grow more sophisticated, and those first machine-languages of infancy just can't be always upwards-compatible. So, even if those early memories were not, in fact, entirely ever lost, they're doomed to become unintelligible, eventually. ------------------------------ Date: 1 Dec 1984 20:03:35 EST From: HARTUNG@USC-ISI.ARPA Subject: PBS & The Brain Hello, I too have been watching the PBS series on the brain. And while I find it to be remarkably up to date, I do have a concern about it. This is a concern not just for this series but for many physiological explanations of experiential phenomena presented to lay audiences. When statements are made that such and such an area of the brain is responsible for some known effect, or that damage to location X results in some new and peculiar observed behavior, these statements are (I fear) taken in a way they are not meant to be. The lay audience has a different frame of reference than a psychologist or neurophysiologist. Scientists studying brain functions view their subjects as complex models involving the interaction of a variety of known components: neurotransmiters; ganglia; axon projections; structures, etc. The majority of the audiance has only limited exposure to these objects and concepts and not enough time to really develop a similar framework to view all this new knowledge in. Instead I believe they do what people usually do when under- standing new material and that is relate it to what they already know. What people already know is that their brain is responsible for their subjective awareness of the world. And as a result of the attempt to integrate knowledge about the brain with the fact that it is the seat of subjective experience there is a strong possibility that people will believe that these explanations of brain functioning are in fact explanations of how it is that they have an experiential component to their lives. Such physiological explanations will probably never supply the answer to the question of how it is that we have the kind of experience of things that we do. For good argument on this point I refer you to Nagel's article in the Oct. '74 Philsophical Review "What is it like to be a bat?". But, lay audiences are rarely if ever informed of this. Another point frequently skipped in presenting brain physiology to lay audiences is the great importance of subjective experience in the functioning of cognition. (See Natsoulas, T. Residual Subjectivity. American Psychologist March 1978.) Indeed subjectivity is so inseparable from cognition that it raises serious questions about the capacity of digital machines to perform the full range of human abilities, given that such digital machines may not be able to achieve a subjective perspective (Searle, J. Minds, Brains, and Programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Vol. 3, No. 3). Arguments concerning the mind brain problem have even come to doubt the capacity of present scientific approaches to the study of mental phenomena and their relationship to physical phenomena to have any success (Fodor, J.A. Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences Vol. 3 No. 3). I assume that the AI-LIST audience is aware of details of these arguments. The television audience mostly is not. I understand the reluctance of television producers to include arguments as abstract and difficult as those on the mind-brain problem. Not to mention the fact that certain religious groups find them upsetting. However, I feel it is important for us who are scientists, to encourage people consulting us about presentations they would make to lay people, to provide the broadest possible context for our arguments, and always to remember who our audience is and how different their perspective may be. Michael A. Moran Lockheed Advanced Software Laboratory address HARTUNG@USC-ISI ------------------------------ Date: Wed 5 Dec 84 21:28:17-PST From: Dikran Karagueuzian <DIKRAN@SU-CSLI.ARPA> Subject: Seminars - Speech & Language & Memory & Math Representation (CSLI) [Excerpted from the CSLI Newsletter by Laws@SRI-AI.] ABSTRACT OF NEXT WEEK'S SEMINAR ``A Generalized Framework for Speech Recognition'' This talk will describe a framework for speaker-independent, large-vocabulary and/or continuous speech recognition being developed at Schlumberger (Fairchild). The framework consists of three components: 1) a finite-state pronunciation network which models relevant acoustic-phonetic events in the recognition vocabulary; 2) a set of generalized acoustic pattern matchers; and 3) an optimal search strategy based on a dynamic programming algorithm. The framework is designed to accommodate a variety of (typically disparate) approaches to the speech recognition problem, including spectral template matching, acoustic-phonetic feature extraction and lexical pruning based on broad-category segmentation. A working system developed within this framework and tailored to the digits vocabulary will also be described. The system achieves high recognition accuracy on a corpus spoken by approximately 250 talkers from 22 ``dialect groups'' within the continental United States. ---Marcia Bush ____________ ABSTRACT OF NEXT WEEK'S COLLOQUIUM ``Data Semantics'' Abstract: There is a growing agreement of opinion that several semantic phenomena can only be adequately dealt with in a theory which takes partiality seriously, a theory of partial objects. There is no agreement about what these partial objects are; for instance, whether they represent ``pieces of the world'' or ``states of partial information about the world.'' Yet, the choice of the perspective determines in large part the potential of the theory. I will discuss various aspects of Data Semantics, a theory being developed by Frank Veltman and me, which takes the second perspective as basic: the semantic behavior of several types of expressions can best be understood if we take them to relate to our lack of information, and regard them as patterns on how information can grow. I will argue that problems concerning quantification and equality force us to distinguish between different kinds of partial objects. ---Fred Landman F1 (AND F3) PROJECT MEETING Title: Self-propagating Search of Memory Speaker: Pentti Kanerva Time/Date: Tuesday, December 11, 3:15 p.m. Place: Ventura Seminar Room Abstract: Human memory has been compared to a film library that is indexed by the contents of the film strips stored in it. How might one construct a computer memory that would allow the computer (a robot) to recognize patterns and to recall sequences the way humans do? The model presented is a simple generalization of the conventional random-access memory of a computer. However, it differs from it in that (1) the address space is very large (e.g., 1,000-bit addresses), (2) only a small number of physical locations are needed to realize the memory, (3) a pattern is stored by adding it into a SET of locations, and (4) a pattern is retrieved by POOLING the contents of a set of locations. Patterns (e.g., of 1,000 bits) are stored in the memory (the memory locations are 1,000 bits wide) and they are also used to address the memory. From such a memory it is possible to retrieve previously stored patterns by approximate retrieval cues--thus, the memory is sensitive to similarities. By storing a sequence of patterns as a linked list, it is possible to index into any part of any "film strip" and to follow the strip from that point on (recalling a sequence). ____________ AREA C MEETING Topic: Theories of variable types for mathematical practice, with computational interpretations Speaker: Solomon Feferman, Depts. of Mathematics and Philosophy Time/Date: 1:30-3:30 p.m., Wednesday, December 12 Place: Conference Room, Ventura Hall Abstract: A new class of formal systems is set up with the following characteristics: 1) Significant portions of current mathematical practice (such as in algebra and analysis) can be formalized naturally within them. 2) The systems have standard set-theoretical interpretations. 3) They also have direct computational interpretations, in which all functions are partial recursive. 4) The proof-theoretical strengths of these systems are surprisingly weak (e.g. one is of strength Peano arithmetic). Roughly speaking, these are axiomatic theories of partial functions and classes. The latter serve as types for elements and functions, but they may be variable (or "abstract") as well as constant. In addition, an element may fall under many types ("polymorphism"). Nevertheless, a form of typed lambda calculus can be set up to define functions. The result 3) gets around some of the problems that have been met with the interpretation of the polymorphic lambda calculus in recent literature on abstract data types. Its proof requires a new generalization of the First Recursion Theorem, which may have independent interest. The result 4) is of philosophical interest, since it undermines arguments for impredicative principles on the grounds of necessity for mathematics (and, in turn, for physics). There are simple extensions of these theories, not meeting condition 2), in which there is a type of all types, so that operations on types appear simply as special kinds of functions. NL1 MEETING Topic: ``Association with Focus'' Speaker: Mats Rooth Time/Date: 2 p.m., Friday, December 7 Place: Trailer Seminar Room Note: The content will overlap with but be non-identical to the presentation the speaker gave in the intonation seminar. Abstract: In the context of adverbs of quantification, conditionals, and ``only,'' focus can have truth conditional significance. Suppose Mary introduced Bill and Tom to Sue and performed no other introductions. Then ``Mary only introduced Bill to SUE'' is true, while ``Mary only introduced BILL to Sue'' is false. Similarly, ``MARY always takes Sue to the movies'' and ``Mary always takes SUE to the movies'' have different truth conditions. My general claim is that focus influences truth conditions indirectly: the semantics of the constructions in question involve contextual parameters, typically unspecified domains of quantification, which are fixed by a focus-influenced component of meaning. This idea is executed in a Montague grammar framework. ------------------------------ Date: Fri, 7 Dec 84 10:36:07 EST From: Morton A Hirschberg <mort@BRL-BMD.ARPA> Subject: Conference - Intelligent Systems and Machines CALL FOR PAPERS 1985 Conference on Intelligent Systems and Machines Dates: April 23-24, 1985 Place: Oakland University Rochester, Michigan Technical papers reflecting both advances and applications in all aspects of intelligent systems and machines will be considered. Suggested topics include, but are not restricted to: Intelligent Robotics, Machine Intelligence, C3I, Adaptive Control and Estimation, Visual Perception and Computer Vision, Pattern Recognition and Image Processing, Artificial Intelligence for Engineering Design, Intelligent Simulation Tools, Computer-Integrated Manufacturing Systems, Knowledge Representation, Expert Systems, Game Theory and Military Strategy, Interpretation of Multisensor Information, Automatic Message Understanding, Natural Language and Automatic Programming. Authors are requested to submit a 300-500 word abstract by January 31, 1985 to: Professor Nan K. Loh, Conference Chairman, (313)377-2222 Professor Christian Wagner, Technical Review Committee Chairman (313)377-2215 Center for Robotics and Advanced Automation School for Engineering and Computer Science Oakland University Rochester, Michigan 48063 The conference will be preceded by tutorials on AI and Robotics held 22 April. ------------------------------ End of AIList Digest ********************
bwm@ccice2.UUCP (Brad Miller) (12/10/84)
> Date: Thu, 6 Dec 1984 01:59 EST > From: MINSKY%MIT-OZ@MIT-MC.ARPA > Subject: Infant Amnesia V2 #165 > > ... I like theories like this: our experience is first > encoded in rather stupid ways; a square is seen as a line attached to > another line attached to another line, etc. Like an early > assembly-language. Later, a square is represented as "closed path of > equal lines" and, later, orthognal pairs of parallels, etc. -- going > to Fortrams to Pascals to LOGs to SMALLTalks to who-knows-what. The > representatins and their interpreters grow more sophisticated, and > those first machine-languages of infancy just can't be always > upwards-compatible. So, even if those early memories were not, in > fact, entirely ever lost, they're doomed to become > unintelligible, eventually. This doesn't explain how someone with an edictic or photographic memory can examine a scene after being exposed to it and discover things about it. The theory I like says that memories of scenes or situations are stored as holograms. We simply garbage-collect our earlier memories due to lack of access, that is, we haven't stored them as instances of anything, so there are no pointers to them. Brad Miller -- ...[rochester, cbrma, rlgvax, ritcv]!ccice5!ccice2!bwm
kay@flame.UUCP (Kay Dekker) (12/15/84)
[my, that was a yummy bug-fix!] Brad Miller in <532@ccice2.UUCP> says: >This doesn't explain how someone with an edictic or photographic memory >can examine a scene after being exposed to it and discover things about it. Sorry, but I wasn't aware that eidetic memeory had been shown to exist. Am I out-of-date, people? Kay -- "But what we need to know is, do people want nasally-insertable computers?" ... mcvax!ukc!flame!kay