[net.politics] Freedom, coercion, and free markets

carnes@gargoyle.UChicago.UUCP (Richard Carnes) (01/22/85)

There has been a good deal of discussion recently in net.politics on the
subject of freedom and its relation to free-market systems, with
libertarians and their allies generally taking the position that the market
supports and is necessary for freedom.  The best discussion of this question
that I am aware of is in Charles E. Lindblom, *Politics and Markets:  The
World's Political-Economic Systems*, a book I highly recommend to anyone
with an interest in the title subject.  I hope it is obvious that in quoting
from Lindblom I am not quoting an "authority" to silence opposition, but
rather I am presenting his arguments for your consideration in hopes of
promoting a more informed and intelligent discussion of this topic.  It
would be a pointless waste of labor to paraphrase Lindblom, so I will simply
lift whole paragraphs from his chapter entitled "Exchange and Markets."
_________________

The classical liberal case for market systems declares:  Liberty through the
market; no liberty without.  True?  No one understands market systems until
he appreciates how many good, though conflicting, answers can be given to
that simple question.  Beginning with parental control in infancy, no one
ever escapes social control.  "Freedom" and "liberty" denote situations in
which controls are not absent but are in some sense acceptable.  Whether,
then, the market supports freedom raises questions about its characteristic
forms of control.

According to the [classical] liberal argument in the tradition of Locke,
Smith, the Mills, Spencer, and Dicey, in a market system one responds--for
example, takes a particular job--only if the proffered benefits are
attractive, hence only if one voluntarily chooses to do so.  In an authority
system one is required to work where assigned and obey any other command
regardless of benefit.  As some people see it, no more needs to be said to
prove men freer in markets than in authority systems.

An immediate objection to that line of argument is that it simply ignores
the effect of a transaction on persons not a party to it--those who must
endure the smell of a new factory in the area, the noise of motorcycles
breaking the quiet of their neighborhood, or the risk of accident in a
nuclear power plant.  In a market system, they make no free choice; these
effects are imposed upon them.  

Third-party or external effects aside, the argument does not hold even for
the parties immediate to the transaction, who are regarded as voluntarily
entering into exchange with each other.  Let us see why.

PROPERTY.  How much I can accomplish and how effectively I can protect
myself through exchange depends in large part on what I own and can offer in
exchange.  A hidden assumption in the conventional argument is that private
property, on which exchange rests, does not itself constitute a barrier to
freedom and is, in addition, noncoercively established and perpetuated.  If
one imagines a small society sharing assets collectively which is then
transformed, by assignment of every asset to some one individual, into a
society practicing exchange among owners of private property--and with
grossly unequal distribution of the assets to individuals--it is not at all
obvious that free exchange makes (or leaves) the less propertied members of
that society free.  And if the move from collective to private ownership is
imposed by strong men who forcibly take the lion's share of the assets,
clearly no simple argument leads to the conclusion that subsequent exchanges
among them, however free, make those who have little property free.  Nor if
we are all born into a world in which property rights are already assigned,
as indeed they are, does it follow that exchange supports our freedom unless
we own a great deal.  

This objection to the liberal argument does not depend on how in actual fact
private property was historically established, how it is in fact maintained,
or whether it is a good institution.  The objection rests on logic.  The
traditional liberal argument is incomplete unless it defends private
property as itself consistent with freedom, a point on which it is silent.
[Author's footnote:  In both Friedman, *Capitalism and Freedom*, and Hayek,
*Road to Serfdom*, the possible coerciveness of the distribution of property
is not discussed.  Frank H. Knight argues that the history of the
distribution of property undermines the claim that freedom leads to
desirable results, but he does not consider the possibility that it may
itself undercut the claim that market relations are free (in *Freedom and
Reform*).]  It [the traditional liberal argument] is simply blind to the
implications for freedom of Proudhon's "Property is theft!" as well as to
implications of less extreme interpretations of how property is established
and maintained.  [Author's footnote:  Formally, the same objection can be
brought against the liberal position that, leaving property aside, exchange
of services makes men free because they will respond through exchange of
services only when they voluntarily choose to do so.  Some distribution of
skills among persons would make some men greatly dependent on others--for an
extreme example, if only a few persons could fight and thus defend
themselves and others.  The favored persons could extract, as a price for
their services, concessions from the others inconsistent with their freedom,
however freedom is defined.  Again, whether historically this is or is not
the case, the liberal argument simply fails to examine the implications for
freedom of distribution of skills.]

Another way to put the point is this.  In liberal thought a world of
exchange is conflict-free.  Everyone does what he wishes.  When all social
coordination is through voluntary exchange, no one imposes his will on
anyone else.  But how, we ask, can such a happy state be possible?  It is
possible only because the conflicts over who gets what have already been
settled through a distribution of property rights in the society.  Was that
distribution conflict-free?  Obviously not.  Was it noncoercively achieved?
Obviously not.  The distribution of wealth in contemporary England, for
example, is a consequence of centuries of conflict, including Viking raids,
the Norman Conquest, the early authority of Crown and nobility, two waves of
dispossession of agricultural labor from the land, and the law of
inheritance.  --Charles E. Lindblom

[To be continued]
Richard Carnes, ihnp4!gargoyle!carnes

gam@amdahl.UUCP (gam) (01/24/85)

> = [ from "Politics and Markets: The World's Political-Economic System",
>   by Charles E. Lindblom ]

Throughout your excerpt, Lindblom's arguments are rather abstract.  He
explains how things "ought to work" by "logic", but he is so wrapped
up in his hypotheses he never bothers to look at how the real world
works. The best he can do is vague reference to the real world in the
case of England, and even then doesn't examine it much.

What Lindblom is ignoring is that people *create* wealth, they don't
just inherit it.  But we'll get to that.  He also tends to view
situations as static rather than dynamic.  Thinks are *instantaneously*
bad, so the free market is a failure.  Here is an example:

> An immediate objection to [free transactions] is that it simply ignores
> the effect of a transaction on persons not a party to it--those who must
> endure the smell of a new factory in the area, the noise of motorcycles
> breaking the quiet of their neighborhood, or the risk of accident in a
> nuclear power plant.  In a market system, they make no free choice; these
> effects are imposed upon them.  

If people don't like the neighborhood, they leave.  When people leave
they take their property with them.  This produces a decline of wealth
for the area.  It is not in the interests of people wanting to maintain
a lively economy to encourage the native wealth to leave.

People are also less likely to move *into* undesirable areas, so the
influx of wealth is cut off.

Lindblom makes his hypothesis (which sounds good) but fails to follow
thru with the *REAL* consequences of ignoring the effects on "persons
not a party to it".

Let's face it -- do *you* want to move to Gary, Indiana?

>         ...How much I can accomplish and how effectively I can protect
> myself through exchange depends in large part on what I own and can offer in
> exchange....

So far so good.

>         ...A hidden assumption in the conventional argument is that private
> property, on which exchange rests, does not itself constitute a barrier to
> freedom ...

This is a set-up.  Lindblom says that the "exchange" is of "private
property"!  He has decided to ignore that individuals can make money
by WORK without even owning private property.

Remember WWII, when the Japanese on the West Coast had all their
property taken away and they were incarcerated?  (Even then they were
as a group successful and propertied, which some believe was part of
the motivation for their incarcertion).  So, they come out after the
war with nothing.  What happens?  By 1969, Japanese-Americans as a
group had family incomes of 132% of the national average!
(Anglo-Saxons were at 105%).  Many now own *their own businesses*!

Why did this happen? They *worked*!  They exchanged their skills for
money, they did a good job and were reliable.  They're property
owners again!

Amazing, isn't it?

But Lindblom goes right on abstracting ....

> If
> one imagines a small society sharing assets collectively which is then
> transformed, by assignment of every asset to some one individual, into a
> society practicing exchange among owners of private property--and with
> grossly unequal distribution of the assets to individuals--it is not at all
> obvious that free exchange makes (or leaves) the less propertied members of
> that society free.

Looks pretty foolish, now, doesn't it?  Again, he ignores the value of
work (human capital) completely.

I suppose I've made my point but I want to poke at Lindblom a bit more:

> This objection to the liberal argument does not depend on how in actual fact
> private property was historically established, how it is in fact maintained,
> or whether it is a good institution.  The objection rests on logic.

Nice technique, eh?  "If you disagree with this you are being illogical.
Besides, I have a PhD."

> The
> traditional liberal argument is incomplete unless it defends private
> property as itself consistent with freedom, a point on which it is silent.

Private property *IS* consistent with freedom, but Lindblom just can't
see that *human capital* creates wealth that can *buy* property!

But here is a token argument against even that principle:

> Some distribution of
> skills among persons would make some men greatly dependent on others-

Isn't that why we are social creatures to begin with? (*sheesh!*)

> for an
> extreme example, if only a few persons could fight and thus defend
> themselves and others.  The favored persons could extract, as a price for
> their services, concessions from the others inconsistent with their freedom,
> however freedom is defined. 

(Right, like, I'd like to get my food for free, but those fascist
store owners are making me *pay* for it!  Can you imagine?!  I'm
calling the ACLU!)

Then fighters would be highly paid -- for a while.  Then others
would train themselves to fight as well ("it's a high-paying, rewarding
career!").  But then there are more fighters.  The Incredible Hulk
is charging $50 an hour, but Hercules will fight off barbarians
for only $45 an hour.  Economic competition ensues.  Prices drop.
The free market solves yet another problem.

Say, isn't Computer Science a hot major in college these days .... ?

If all products and services were "free", how would you propose to
allocate them?  By lots?  By perceived need?  By "want"?  By
nepotism...?

"Politics offers 'free' benefits for people to fight over.  Markets
put prices on benefits, forcing each group to limit its own use of them,
thereby in effect sharing with others.  A society with both Buddhist and
Islamic citizens must somehow allocate its available building materials
in such a way as to have these materials share in the building of
temples and mosques.  If the building materials are shared through
economic processes, each set of religious followers weighs the cost
agains benefits and limits its demand accordingly.  But if these same
building materials are provided free or otherwise shared through
political processes, each group has the incentive to demand the
lion's share -- or all -- of the materials for building its own
place of worship, which is always more urgently needed, in more
grandious proportions, than the other."
[ Thomas Sowell, "The Economics and Politics of Race" ]
-- 
Gordon A. Moffett		...!{ihnp4,hplabs,sun}!amdahl!gam

josh@topaz.ARPA (J Storrs Hall) (01/25/85)

> This objection to the liberal argument does not depend on how in actual fact
> private property was historically established, how it is in fact maintained,
> or whether it is a good institution.  The objection rests on logic. 
...

> Another way to put the point is this.  In liberal thought a world of
> exchange is conflict-free.  Everyone does what he wishes.  When all social
> coordination is through voluntary exchange, no one imposes his will on
> anyone else.  But how, we ask, can such a happy state be possible?  It is
> possible only because the conflicts over who gets what have already been
> settled through a distribution of property rights in the society.  Was that
> distribution conflict-free?  Obviously not.  Was it noncoercively achieved?
> Obviously not.  The distribution of wealth in contemporary England, for
> example, is a consequence of centuries of conflict, including Viking raids,
> the Norman Conquest, the early authority of Crown and nobility, two waves of
> dispossession of agricultural labor from the land, and the law of
> inheritance.  --Charles E. Lindblom
> 
> Richard Carnes, ihnp4!gargoyle!carnes


Do I detect the slightest hint of a self-contradiction here?

I (and one assumes most of the propertarians reading this) am well
aware of the limitations on one's freedom which occur because most
of the world is owned by other people.  However, you (and lindblom)
are making the implicit comparison to someone who owns everything,
and thus coming to the conclusion that a scantily-propertied person
is unfree.  If we compare it instead to the Socialist ideal wherein
the person owns nothing, you will see that even a pauper in a 
capitalist state is better off than a hero of labor in a socialist
one.

The basic question which the collectivist must answer is whether
there is any way of a group owning something as a group.  You are
well aware, I'm sure, of the various political power structures which
actually own everything in the cases where it is supposedly owned
by "the people".  I submit that the actual ownership of all property
by a small power group is MORE inequitable than the statistically
skewed distribution which occurs under capitalism.

--JoSH