[net.physics] Thermodynamics and probability

gjphw@ihuxm.UUCP (03/24/84)

                                 Hold on here!!

   In response to a question seeking clarification of the concepts around
 thermodynamics and probability, two well written articles were submitted
 (D. Mitchell and J. Stekas).  I would like to make a request for consideration
 of an alternate view.

   I would like to suggest that there are two major schools of thought about
 the connection between probability (statistical mechanics) and thermodynamics.
 The view with the overwhelming number of adherents holds that dynamics
 (classical and quantum) is exact and thermodynamics is an approximation (in
 addition to being an idealization).  Dynamics is the basis for statistical
 mechanics, and the usual source for the more fundamental understanding of the
 laws of thermodynamics comes from this study.  A popular graduate level text
 on statistical mechanics (Huang) states that the second law of thermodynamics
 (entropy) is an approximation.  The support of a bias toward dynamics is the
 outstanding success that can be realized using dynamical explanations for
 single particle interactions.

   A distinctly minority view, with support among some physical chemists, is
 that thermodynamics is exact and dynamics (or at least statistical mechanics)
 is an approximation.  The major spokesman for this view is I. Prigogine in
 such texts as *From Being to Becoming*.  In the experience of people who deal
 with large many body systems (N > 10^23), thermodynamics has never been
 observed to be violated and typical single particle dynamics is inadequate for
 the task of description.  Prigogine (who is not a particularly lucid writer)
 argues that dynamics and statistical mechanics need modifications to bring
 them in agreement with thermodynamics (especially the second law).  Non-
 equilibrium statistical mechanics might demonstrate the shortcomings of a
 dynamics only description, except for the fact that most expressions for these
 situations are too difficult to solve for the general case.

   You might be tempted to take your pick of these two schools with the
proviso that the current consensus holds with the preeminence of dynamics.
In the realm of large many body systems (e.g., a room full of air), the
adequacy of single particle dynamics is not so clear.
-- 

                                    Patrick Wyant
                                    AT&T Bell Laboratories (Naperville, IL)
                                    *!ihuxm!gjphw

gwyn@brl-vgr.ARPA (Doug Gwyn ) (03/25/84)

But every time someone peeks at the microbehavior of a macro system
such as a room full of air, he sees the micro-laws of physics being
obeyed (no flames about the incompleteness of our knowledge of the
laws, please).  This is overwhelming confirmation for the consensus
view of thermodynamics as statistical physics.

One important point about physical understanding that was not
emphasized in the schools I went to, but should have been, is that
different points of view are more or less suitable for dealing with
different situations.  Trying to apply one single tool such as
deterministic dynamics to all situations will get one in trouble
(for lack of computational resources, if for no other reason).

alan@entropy.UUCP (Alan King) (03/27/84)

concerning a close look at a room full of air:

Isn't the result of a close look at air or liquids the
starting point for the development of Brownian motion?
Once you begin examining things that small with that much
energy, the paths are not even differentiable!  Thus it
is hard to see the justification for the comment that
dynamical laws explain motion in the microscale.  To put it
another way: there is no interval of time of positive length
during which an individual molecule of air travels along
a "classical" trajectory.  The path is known only in a 
statistical sense even for individual particles.  Of course
the dynamical laws must be obeyed -- but they cannot be used
to explain the motion of individual particles in a swarm of air.
It was the attempt to explain this motion that led Einstein
to develop his explanation of Brownian motion.

alan king 
dept of mathematcs
university of washington

mam@charm.UUCP (Matthew Marcus) (03/31/84)

Entropy!alan claims that the paths of molecules in gases aren't even differentiable,
much less explainable by micro-dynamic.  Sorry, that's rubbish!  True, if
you look *at a certain length scale*, the paths appear pretty noisy, but they
are quite continuous and differentiable when examined with resolution below
the mean free path.  For a hard-sphere gas, the path is non-differentiable
at the collision points, but there's no such thing as a hard-sphere gas,
except inside a computer.  That reminds me, lots pf people use molecular
dynamics (integrating micro equations of motion on a computer) to explain
macro properties of gases, liquids, and solids.
	{BTL}!charm!mam

gwyn@brl-vgr.ARPA (Doug Gwyn ) (03/31/84)

Sorry to poke a hole in your argument but molecular motion in a gas is
not "fractal".  Look up "mean free path" and you will see what I mean.

mwg@allegra.UUCP (Mark Garrett) (04/10/84)

	No; all the air molecles in a room could not, by themselves, move
to one side.  Statistical mechanics inherently is not accurate enough (nor
has it been verified experimentally accurately enough) to predict correctly
such improbable events as all air molecules *by themselves* drifting to one 
side of the room.  Although the examples--(1) a growing crystal, or (2) a
gravitational dust cloud condensing into planets, of (3) chemical processes
that formed life--represent increases in entropy and at the same time
increases in order, nevertheless these examples all occur at the expense of
even more disorder (simultaneouus irreversible processes) in the universe:
(1) heat flow from hot to cold bodies, (2) emmitted noise and other
radiation, as well as conversion of (ordered) potential gravitational energy
into (disordered) heat, and (3) consumption of nuclear fuel on the sun.
	Besides, statistical mechanics rests upon the assmpution of the truth
of the ergodic (or quasi-ergodic) hypothesis--i.e., the hypothesis that the
universe comes back to its initial state (or as closely so as can be
specified) or to any other given state (or closely so) if only you wait
long enough.  This hypothesis is obviously false.  After you die, the
universe will never, repeat *never*, comeback to its present state (or closely
so)--i.e., with all calendars on the earth displaying a year "1984" (or
"1914") and with you alive (except that you are insane).

			-D.I. Caplan
			 Bell Labs, Murray Hill

{this opinion represents neither that of this coropration or even the
owner of this account}

steve@Brl-Bmd.ARPA (04/15/84)

From:      Stephen Wolff <steve@Brl-Bmd.ARPA>

>>	From: hplabs!tektronix!uw-beaver!uw-june!entropy!alan@Ucb-Vax.ARPA
>>
>>	Isn't the result of a close look at air or liquids the
>>	starting point for the development of Brownian motion?
>>	Once you begin examining things that small with that much
>>	energy, the paths are not even differentiable!

Oh, baloney!  These aren't small particles you're talking about - they're
m o l e c u l e s !  The paths are for ALL intents and purposes classical.
The ABSTRACTION called `Brownian motion' or the `Wiener process' is just
that - a very pretty passage to a `conceptual limit' of molecular motion.

It's the ABSTRACTION that has all the lovely properties - almost
everywhere non-differentiabilty, linearly growing variance, independent
increments, the lot - but the REAL process ain't so accommodating.